Switch to: Citations

References in:

A pragmatic defense of Millianism

Philosophical Studies 138 (2):271 - 289 (2008)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics and Modal Logic.Rudolf Carnap - 1947 - Chicago, IL, USA: University of Chicago Press.
    This is identical with the first edition (see 21: 2716) except for the addition of a Supplement containing 5 previously published articles and the bringing of the bibliography (now 73 items) up to date. The 5 added articles present clarifications or modifications of views expressed in the first edition. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2009 APA, all rights reserved).
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   335 citations  
  • Synonymity.L. Linsky - 1967 - In Paul Edwards (ed.), The Encyclopedia of philosophy. New York,: Macmillan. pp. 8.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics and Modal Logic.Rudolf Carnap - 1947 - Chicago, IL, USA: University of Chicago Press.
    "This book is valuable as expounding in full a theory of meaning that has its roots in the work of Frege and has been of the widest influence.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   683 citations  
  • Criteria of Intensionality.J. O. Urmson & Jonathan Cohen - 1968 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 42 (1):107-142.
  • The puzzle of Hesperus and Phosphorus.Michael Tye - 1978 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 56 (3):219 – 224.
  • Do conversational implicatures explain substitutivity failures?Cara Spencer - 2006 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 87 (1):126–139.
    The Russellian approach to the semantics of attitude ascriptions faces a problem in explaining the robust speaker intuitions that it does not predict. A familiar response to the problem is to claim that utterances of attitude ascriptions may differ in their Gricean conversational implicatures. I argue that the appeal to Grice is ad hoc. First, we find that speakers do not typically judge an utterance false merely because it implicates something false. The apparent cancellability of the putative implicatures is irrelevant, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Review: Reply to Critics. [REVIEW]S. Soames - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 128 (3):711 - 738.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Reply to Critics.S. Soames - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 128 (3):711-738.
    Linsky’s central point is correct; Kripke’s distinction between rigid and nonrigid designators can be extended in a straightforward way from singular terms to general terms. In both cases, for an expression to rigidly designate its extension is for it to designate the same extension with respect to every possible world-state (in which it has an extension at all). On this account, simple natural kind terms like water, gold, electricity, blue, and tiger – as well as ordinary general terms like bachelor, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century Vol. 2: The Age of Meaning.Scott Soames - 2003 - Princeton University Press.
    This is a major, wide-ranging history of analytic philosophy since 1900, told by one of the tradition's leading contemporary figures. The first volume takes the story from 1900 to mid-century. The second brings the history up to date.
  • Beyond Rigidity: Reply to McKinsey.Scott Soames - 2005 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 35 (1):169 - 178.
    Michael McKinsey raises several important and far-reaching issues in his critical examination of Beyond Rigidity. I am happy to have a chance to respond, and thereby, I hope, to advance the debate.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Beyond rigidity: the unfinished semantic agenda of Naming and necessity.Scott Soames - 2002 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    In this fascinating work, Scott Soames offers a new conception of the relationship between linguistic meaning and assertions made by utterances. He gives meanings of proper names and natural kind predicates and explains their use in attitude ascriptions. He also demonstrates the irrelevance of rigid designation in understanding why theoretical identities containing such predicates are necessary, if true.
  • Kripke’s Revenge.Theodore Sider & David Braun - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 128 (3):669-682.
    Kripke's objections to descriptivism may be modified to apply to Scott Soames's pragmatic account from his book Beyond Rigidity. Further, intuitions about argument-validity threaten any theory in the vicinity of Soames's.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Putnam on Synonymity and Belief.W. Sellars - 1954 - Analysis 15 (5):117-120.
  • Putnam on Synonymity and Belief.Rulon Wells - 1955 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 20 (3):295-295.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Putnam on Synonymity and Belief.W. Sellars - 1955 - Analysis 15 (5):117-117.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The 'fido'-fido theory of belief.Stephen Schiffer - 1987 - Philosophical Perspectives 1:455-480.
  • The pragmatics of attitude ascription.Jennifer M. Saul - 1998 - Philosophical Studies 92 (3):363-389.
  • Illogical Belief.Nathan Salmon - 1989 - Philosophical Perspectives 3:243-285.
    A sequel to the author’s book /Frege’s Puzzle/ (1986).
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   106 citations  
  • On a Fregean Argument for the Distinctness of Sense and Reference.R. M. Sainsbury - 1983 - Analysis 43 (1):12 - 14.
  • Review: Meaning and Attitude Ascriptions. [REVIEW]M. Richard - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 128 (3):683 - 709.
  • Meaning and Attitude Ascriptions.M. Richard - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 128 (3):683-709.
  • Defective Contexts, Accommodation, and Normalization.Mark Richard - 1995 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 25 (4):551 - 570.
    Propositional Attitudes defends an account of ‘believes’ on which the verb is contextually sensitive. x believes that S says that x has a belief which is ‘well rendered’ or acceptably translated by S; since contextually variable information about what makes for a good translation helps determine the extension of ‘believes,’ the verb is contextually sensitive. Sider and Soames criticize this account. They say it has unacceptable consequences in cases in which we make multiple ascriptions of belief to a single individual (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Literal Meaning.François Récanati - 2002 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    According to the dominant position among philosophers of language today, we can legitimately ascribe determinate contents to natural language sentences, independently of what the speaker actually means. This view contrasts with that held by ordinary language philosophers fifty years ago: according to them, speech acts, not sentences, are the primary bearers of content. François Recanati argues for the relevance of this controversy to the current debate about semantics and pragmatics. Is 'what is said' determined by linguistic conventions, or is it (...)
  • Literal Meaning. [REVIEW]Kent Bach - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (2):487-492.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   292 citations  
  • Synonymity and the Analysis of Belief Sentences.Hilary Putnam - 1953 - Analysis 14 (5):114 - 122.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Synonymity, and the Analysis of Belief Sentences.Hilary Putnam - 1955 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 20 (3):293-294.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The principle of semantic compositionality.Francis Jeffry Pelletier - 1994 - Topoi 13 (1):11-24.
    The Principle of Semantic Compositionality (sometimes called Frege''s Principle) is the principle that the meaning of a (syntactically complex) whole is a function only of the meanings of its (syntactic) parts together with the manner in which these parts were combined. This principle has been extremely influential throughout the history of formal semantics; it has had a tremendous impact upon modern linguistics ever since Montague Grammars became known; and it has more recently shown up as a guiding principle for a (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Names in and out of thought.Peter Pagin - 1992 - Philosophical Studies 66 (1):27 - 51.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Saving substitutivity in simple sentences.Joseph G. Moore - 1999 - Analysis 59 (2):91–105.
  • Did Clinton lie?Joseph G. Moore - 2000 - Analysis 60 (3):250-254.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • On proper names in belief ascriptions.Thomas McKay - 1981 - Philosophical Studies 39 (3):287-303.
  • Critical Notice of Scott Soames, Beyond Rigidity. [REVIEW]Michael McKinsey - 2005 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 35 (1):169-178.
    In this admirable book, Scott Soames provides well defended answers to some of the most difficult and important questions in the philosophy of language, and he does so with characteristic thoroughness, clarity, and rigor. The book's title is appropriate, since it does indeed go ‘beyond rigidity’ in many ways. Among other things, Soames does the following in the course of the book. He persuasively argues that the main thesis of Kripke's Naming and Necessity—that ordinary names are rigid designators—can be extended (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Critical Notice.Michael Mckinsey - 2005 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 35 (1):149-168.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Synonymity.Benson Mates - 1954 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 19 (3):223-223.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • Interpreted Logical Forms.Richard K. Larson & Peter Ludlow - 1993 - Synthese 95 (3):305 - 355.
  • Millian descriptivism.Frederick Kroon - 2004 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82 (4):553 – 576.
    Mill is a detractor of the view that proper names have meanings, defending in its place the view that names are nothing more than (meaningless) marks. Because of this, Mill is often regarded as someone who anticipated the theory of direct reference for names: the view that the only contribution a name makes to propositions expressed through its use is the name's referent. In this paper I argue that the association is unfair. With some gentle interpretation, Mill can be portrayed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • How much substitutivity?Graeme Forbes - 1997 - Analysis 57 (2):109–113.
  • Enlightened semantics for simple sentences.G. Forbes - 1999 - Analysis 59 (2):86-91.
  • Simple Sentences, Substitutions, and Mistaken Evaluations.David Braun & Jennifer Saul - 2002 - Philosophical Studies 111 (1):1 - 41.
    Many competent speakers initially judge that (i) is true and (ii) isfalse, though they know that (iii) is true. (i) Superman leaps more tallbuildings than Clark Kent. (ii) Superman leaps more tall buildings thanSuperman. (iii) Superman is identical with Clark Kent. Semanticexplanations of these intuitions say that (i) and (ii) really can differin truth-value. Pragmatic explanations deny this, and say that theintuitions are due to misleading implicatures. This paper argues thatboth explanations are incorrect. (i) and (ii) cannot differ intruth-value, yet (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Intensional isomorphism and identity of belief.Alonzo Church - 1954 - Philosophical Studies 5 (5):65 - 73.
  • Intensional Isomorphism and Identity of Belief.Alonzo Church - 1955 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 20 (3):294-295.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics and Modal Logic.Rudolf Carnap - 1957 - Philosophy of Science 24 (1):92-92.
  • Meaning and synonymy in natural languages.Rudolf Carnap - 1955 - Philosophical Studies 6 (3):33 - 47.
  • Millian descriptivism.Ben Caplan - 2007 - Philosophical Studies 133 (2):181-198.
    In this paper, I argue against Millian Descriptivism: that is, the view that, although sentences that contain names express singular propositions, when they use those sentences speakers communicate descriptive propositions. More precisely, I argue that Millian Descriptivism fares no better (or worse) than Fregean Descriptivism: that is, the view that sentences express descriptive propositions. This is bad news for Millian Descriptivists who think that Fregean Descriptivism is dead.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Belief and synonymy.Tyler Burge - 1978 - Journal of Philosophy 75 (3):119-138.
  • The pragmatics of substitutivity.Jonathan Berg - 1988 - Linguistics and Philosophy 11 (3):355 - 370.
  • Situations and attitudes.Jon Barwise & John Perry - 1981 - Journal of Philosophy 78 (11):668-691.
  • Situations and Attitudes.Jon Barwise & John Perry - 1983 - Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Edited by John Perry.
  • Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts.Kent Bach & Robert M. Harnish - 1979 - Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
    a comprehensive, somewhat Gricean theory of speech acts, including an account of communicative intentions and inferences, a taxonomy of speech acts, and coverage of many topics in pragmatics -/- .
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   371 citations  
  • Frege’s Puzzle (2nd edition).Nathan U. Salmon - 1986 - Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company.
    This is the 1991 (2nd) edition of the 1986 book (MIT Press), considered to be the classic defense of Millianism. The nature of the information content of declarative sentences is a central topic in the philosophy of language. The natural view that a sentence like "John loves Mary" contains information in which two individuals occur as constituents is termed the naive theory, and is one that has been abandoned by most contemporary scholars. This theory was refuted originally by philosopher Gottlob (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   535 citations