Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. What we owe to each other.Thomas Scanlon - 1998 - Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
    In this book, T. M. Scanlon offers new answers to these questions, as they apply to the central part of morality that concerns what we owe to each other.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2435 citations  
  • Consequences and Agent‐Centered Restrictions.G. F. Schuelefer - 1989 - Metaphilosophy 20 (1):77-83.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Consequences and agent-centered restrictions.G. F. Schueler - 1989 - Metaphilosophy 20 (1):77–83.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • I_– _T. M. Scanlon.T. M. Scanlon - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74 (1):301-317.
  • Intention and permissibility, I.T. M. Scanlon - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74 (1):301–317.
    [T. M. Scanlon] It is clearly impermissible to kill one person because his organs can be used to save five others who are in need of transplants. It has seemed to many that the explanation for this lies in the fact that in such cases we would be intending the death of the person whom we killed, or failed to save. What makes these actions impermissible, however, is not the agent's intention but rather the fact that the benefit envisaged does (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Intention and Permissibility, I.Thomas Scanlon - 2000 - Supplement to the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 74 (1):301-317.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Intention and Permissibility.T. M. Scanlon & Jonathan Dancy - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74:301-338.
    [T. M. Scanlon] It is clearly impermissible to kill one person because his organs can be used to save five others who are in need of transplants. It has seemed to many that the explanation for this lies in the fact that in such cases we would be intending the death of the person whom we killed, or failed to save. What makes these actions impermissible, however, is not the agent's intention but rather the fact that the benefit envisaged does (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Intention and Permissibility.T. M. Scanlon & Jonathan Dancy - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74:301-338.
    It is clearly impermissible to kill one person because his organs can be used to save five others who are in need of transplants. It has seemed to many that the explanation for this lies in the fact that in such cases we would be intending the death of the person whom we killed, or failed to save. What makes these actions impermissible, however, is not the agent's intention but rather the fact that the benefit envisaged does not justify an (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Contractualism and aggregation.Sophia Reibetanz - 1998 - Ethics 108 (2):296-311.
    I argue that T.M. Scanlon's contractualist account of morality has difficulty accommodating our intuitions about the moral relevance of the number of people affected by an action. I first consider the "Complaint Model" of reasonable rejection, which restricts the grounds for an individual's rejection of a principle to its effects upon herself. I argue that it can accommodate our intuitions about numbers only if we assume that, whenever we do not know who will be affected, each individual may appeal only (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Deontology and Agency.Piers Rawling - 1993 - The Monist 76 (1):81-100.
    Any adequate account of the distinction between consequentialist and deontological moral systems must take account of the central place given to constraints in the latter. Constraints place limits on what each of us may do in the pursuit of any goal, including the maximisation of the good. There is some debate, however, both over how constraints are to be characterised, and over the rationale for their inclusion in a moral system. Some authors view constraints as agent-relative: a constraint supplies an (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Actions, intentions, and consequences: The doctrine of doing and allowing.Warren S. Quinn - 1989 - Philosophical Review 98 (3):287-312.
  • The consequentialist can recognise rights.Philip Pettit - 1988 - Philosophical Quarterly 38 (150):42-55.
    consequentialist, even being a utilitarian, allows one still to recognise rights.' I believe that these efforts are well motivated, for I think that any moral doctrine is suspect if one of its effects is to make agents unable to take one another's rights seriously.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Consequentialism and respect for persons.Philip Pettit - 1989 - Ethics 100 (1):116-126.
  • Equality and priority.Derek Parfit - 1997 - Ratio 10 (3):202–221.
  • Scanlon and the claims of the many versus the one.Michael Otsuka - 2000 - Analysis 60 (3):288-293.
    In "What We Owe to Each Other", T. M. Scanlon argues that one should save the greater number when faced with the choice between saving one life and two or more different lives. It is, Scanlon claims, a virtue of this argument that it does not appeal to the claims of groups of individuals but only to the claims of individuals. I demonstrate that this argument for saving the greater number, indeed, depends, contrary to what Scanlon says, upon an appeal (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Contractualism and Aggregation.Alastair Norcross - 2002 - Social Theory and Practice 28 (2):303-314.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Moral Individualism: Agent-Relativity and Deontic Restraints.Eric Mack - 1989 - Social Philosophy and Policy 7 (1):81.
    My goal in this essay is to say something helpful about the philosophical foundations of deontic restraints, i.e., moral restraints on actions that are, roughly speaking, grounded in the wrongful character of the actions themselves and not merely in the disvalue of their results. An account of deontic restraints will be formulated and offered against the backdrop of three related, but broader, contrasts or puzzles within moral theory. The plausibility of this account of deontic restraints rests in part on how (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Moral individualism: Agent-relativity and deontic restraints*: Eric Mack.Eric Mack - 1989 - Social Philosophy and Policy 7 (1):81-111.
    My goal in this essay is to say something helpful about the philosophical foundations of deontic restraints, i.e., moral restraints on actions that are, roughly speaking, grounded in the wrongful character of the actions themselves and not merely in the disvalue of their results. An account of deontic restraints will be formulated and offered against the backdrop of three related, but broader, contrasts or puzzles within moral theory. The plausibility of this account of deontic restraints rests in part on how (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Defending the Moral Moderate: Contractualism and Common Sense.Rahul Kumar - 1999 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 28 (4):275-309.
  • Contractualism on saving the many.R. Kumar - 2001 - Analysis 61 (2):165-170.
  • Precis of Morality, Mortality, Vol. 1: Death and Whom to Save from ItMorality, Mortality, Vol. 1: Death and Whom to Save from It. [REVIEW]Frances Kamm - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (4):939.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Owing, justifying, and rejecting. [REVIEW]F. M. Kamm - 2002 - Mind 111 (442):323-354.
  • Morality, Mortality, Vol. 1: Death and Whom to Save from It.Frances Kamm - 1998 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 58 (4):963-967.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Review: Replies to My Critics. [REVIEW]Shelly Kagan - 1991 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (4):919 - 928.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Replies to My Critics. [REVIEW]Shelly Kagan - 1991 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (4):919-928.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Replies to My CriticsThe Limits of Morality.Shelly Kagan - 1991 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (4):919.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Agent-centered restrictions: Clearing the air of paradox.Paul Hurley - 1997 - Ethics 108 (1):120-146.
  • Saving the greater number without combining claims.I. Hirose - 2001 - Analysis 61 (4):341-342.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Contractualism, moral motivation, and practical reason.Samuel Freeman - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy 88 (6):281-303.
    A discussion of T M Scanlon's contractualism as a foundational account of the nature of morality. The article discusses how contractualism provides an account of moral truth and objectivity that is based in an idealization of moral reasoning. It then develops contractualism's account of moral motivation to show how it provides a way to understand obscure but central aspects of Kantian views: the claims that moral reasons are of a special kind, and that moral motives have a basis in practical (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Virtues and Vices.Philippa Foot - 1983 - Noûs 17 (1):117-121.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   232 citations  
  • Satisficing and optimality.Michael Byron - 1998 - Ethics 109 (1):67-93.
    It is common, though perhaps not correct, to think that practical rationality is strictly instrumental.1 The functions of instrumental reason include finding suitable means to our determinate ends, helping to determine our indeterminate ends, and implementing our principles in appropriate actions. One reason that might be given for adopting instrumentalism with respect to rationality might be that our best scientific evidence offers little support for the idea that our brains have powers to detect good and bad as such in persons, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Agency and morality.Richard Brook - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy 88 (4):190-212.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The Demandingness of Scanlon’s Contractualism.Elizabeth Ashford - 2003 - Ethics 113 (2):273-302.
    One of the reasons why Kantian contractualism has been seen as an appealing alternative to utilitarianism is that it seems to be able to avoid utilitarianism's extreme demandingness, while retaining a fully impartial moral point of view. I argue that in the current state of the world, contractualist obligations to help those in need are not significantly less demanding than utilitarian obligations. I also argue that while a plausible version of utilitarianism would be considerably less demanding if the state of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • The End of Welfare As We Know It?Richard J. Arneson - 2002 - Social Theory and Practice 28 (2):315-336.
    A notable achievement of T.M. Scanlon's What We Owe to Each Other is its sustained critique of welfarist consequentialism. Consequentialism is the doctrine that one morally ought always to do an act, of the alternatives, that brings about a state of affairs that is no less good than any other one could bring about. Welfarism is the view that what makes a state of affairs better or worse is some increasing function of the welfare for persons realized in it. I (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Contractualism and Aggregation.Norcross Alastair - 2002 - Social Theory and Practice 28 (2):303-314.
  • Weighing Goods: Equality, Uncertainty and Time.John Broome - 1991 - Wiley-Blackwell.
    This study uses techniques from economics to illuminate fundamental questions in ethics, particularly in the foundations of utilitarianism. Topics considered include the nature of teleological ethics, the foundations of decision theory, the value of equality and the moral significance of a person's continuing identity through time.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   452 citations  
  • Act-Utilitarianism: Account of Right-Making Characteristics or Decision-Making Procedure?R. Eugene Bales - 1971 - American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (3):257 - 265.