Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Special sciences (or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis).J. A. Fodor - 1974 - Synthese 28 (2):97-115.
  • The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation.Ernest Nagel - 1961 - New York, NY, USA: Harcourt, Brace & World.
    Introduction: Science and Common Sense Long before the beginnings of modern civilization, men ac- quired vast funds of information about their environment. ...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   481 citations  
  • On the proper treatment of connectionism.Paul Smolensky - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):1-23.
    A set of hypotheses is formulated for a connectionist approach to cognitive modeling. These hypotheses are shown to be incompatible with the hypotheses underlying traditional cognitive models. The connectionist models considered are massively parallel numerical computational systems that are a kind of continuous dynamical system. The numerical variables in the system correspond semantically to fine-grained features below the level of the concepts consciously used to describe the task domain. The level of analysis is intermediate between those of symbolic cognitive models (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   741 citations  
  • Vision: Variations on Some Berkeleian Themes.Robert Schwartz & David Marr - 1985 - Philosophical Review 94 (3):411.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   749 citations  
  • Approaches to reduction.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1967 - Philosophy of Science 34 (2):137-147.
    Four current accounts of theory reduction are presented, first informally and then formally: (1) an account of direct theory reduction that is based on the contributions of Nagel, Woodger, and Quine, (2) an indirect reduction paradigm due to Kemeny and Oppenheim, (3) an "isomorphic model" schema traceable to Suppes, and (4) a theory of reduction that is based on the work of Popper, Feyerabend, and Kuhn. Reference is made, in an attempt to choose between these schemas, to the explanation of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   228 citations  
  • On language and connectionism: Analysis of a parallel distributed processing model of language acquisition.Steven Pinker & Alan Prince - 1988 - Cognition 28 (1-2):73-193.
  • Two concepts of intertheoretic reduction.Thomas Nickles - 1973 - Journal of Philosophy 70 (April):181-201.
  • The Structure of Science.Ernest Nagel - 1961 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 17 (2):275-275.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   870 citations  
  • Marr’s Three Levels: A Re-evaluation. [REVIEW]Ron McClamrock - 1990 - Minds and Machines 1 (May):185-196.
    the _algorithmic_, and the _implementational_; Zenon Pylyshyn (1984) calls them the _semantic_, the _syntactic_, and the _physical_; and textbooks in cognitive psychology sometimes call them the levels of _content_, _form_, and _medium_ (e.g. Glass, Holyoak, and Santa 1979).
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Intertheoretic relations and the future of psychology.Robert N. McCauley - 1986 - Philosophy of Science 53 (June):179-99.
    In the course of defending both a unified model of intertheoretic relations in science and scientific realism, Paul Churchland has attempted to reinvigorate eliminative materialism. Churchland's eliminativism operates on three claims: (1) that some intertheoretic contexts involve incommensurable theories, (2) that such contexts invariably require the elimination of one theory or the other, and (3) that the relation of psychology and neuroscience is just such a context. I argue that a more detailed account of intertheoretic relations, which distinguishes between the (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Components of high-level vision: A cognitive neuroscience analysis and accounts of neurological syndromes.Stephen M. Kosslyn, Rex A. Flynn, Jonathan B. Amsterdam & Gretchen Wang - 1990 - Cognition 34 (3):203-277.
  • Task Decomposition Through Competition in a Modular Connectionist Architecture: The What and Where Vision Tasks.Robert A. Jacobs, Michael I. Jordan & Andrew G. Barto - 1991 - Cognitive Science 15 (2):219-250.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • M. 1. Jordan, and AG Barto. Task decomposition through competition in a modular connectionist architecture: The what and where vision task. [REVIEW]Robert A. Jacobs - 1990 - Cognitive Science 15 (2):219-250.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Lesioning an attractor network: Investigations of acquired dyslexia.Geoffrey E. Hinton & Tim Shallice - 1991 - Psychological Review 98 (1):74-95.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   151 citations  
  • Special sciences.Jerry A. Fodor - 1974 - Synthese 28 (2):97-115.
  • Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis.Jerry A. Fodor & Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1988 - Cognition 28 (1-2):3-71.
    This paper explores the difference between Connectionist proposals for cognitive a r c h i t e c t u r e a n d t h e s o r t s o f m o d e l s t hat have traditionally been assum e d i n c o g n i t i v e s c i e n c e . W e c l a i m t h a t t h (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1119 citations  
  • Interfield theories.Lindley Darden & Nancy Maull - 1977 - Philosophy of Science 44 (1):43-64.
    This paper analyzes the generation and function of hitherto ignored or misrepresented interfield theories , theories which bridge two fields of science. Interfield theories are likely to be generated when two fields share an interest in explaining different aspects of the same phenomenon and when background knowledge already exists relating the two fields. The interfield theory functions to provide a solution to a characteristic type of theoretical problem: how are the relations between fields to be explained? In solving this problem (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   266 citations  
  • Unity of Science. [REVIEW]William Demopoulos - 1981 - Philosophical Review 90 (1):150-153.
  • Integrating sciences by creating new disciplines: The case of cell biology. [REVIEW]William Bechtel - 1993 - Biology and Philosophy 8 (3):277-299.
    Many studies of the unification of science focus on the theories of different disciplines. The model for integration is the theory reduction model. This paper argues that the embodiment of theories in scientists, and the institutions in which scientists work and the instruments they employ, are critical to the sort of integration that actually occurs in science. This paper examines the integration of scientific endeavors that emerged in cell biology in the period after World War II when the development of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Currents in connectionism.William Bechtel - 1993 - Minds and Machines 3 (2):125-153.
    This paper reviews four significant advances on the feedforward architecture that has dominated discussions of connectionism. The first involves introducing modularity into networks by employing procedures whereby different networks learn to perform different components of a task, and a Gating Network determines which network is best equiped to respond to a given input. The second consists in the use of recurrent inputs whereby information from a previous cycle of processing is made available on later cycles. The third development involves developing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Connectionism and the Mind.William Bechtel & Adele Abrahamsen - 1991 - Wiley-Blackwell.
    Something remarkable is happening in the cognitive sciences. After a quarter of a century of cognitive models that were inspired by the metaphor of the digital computer, the newest cognitive models are inspired by the properties of the brain itself. Variously referred to as connectionist, parallel distributed processing, or neutral network models, they explore the idea that complex intellectual operations can be carried out by large networks of simple, neuron-like units. The units themselves are identical, very low-level and 'stupid'. Intelligent (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • .J. L. McClelland & D. E. Rumelhart (eds.) - 1987 - MIT Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • Vision.David Marr - 1982 - W. H. Freeman.
  • Philosophy of Mind: An Overview for Cognitive Science.William Bechtel - 1988 - Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum.
    Specifically designed to make the philosophy of mind intelligible to those not trained in philosophy, this book provides a concise overview for students and researchers in the cognitive sciences. Emphasizing the relevance of philosophical work to investigations in other cognitive sciences, this unique text examines such issues as the meaning of language, the mind-body problem, the functionalist theories of cognition, and intentionality. As he explores the philosophical issues, Bechtel draws connections between philosophical views and theoretical and experimental work in such (...)
  • Special Sciences, or Disunity of Science as a Working Hypothesis.Jerry Fodor - 1974 - Synthese 28 (2):97--115.
  • Special Sciences.Jerry A. Fodor - 1995 - In Paul K. Moser & J. D. Trout (eds.), Contemporary Materialism: A Reader. London: Routledge. pp. 51-64.
  • Consciousness and the Brain: A Scientific and Philosophical Inquiry.G. G. Globus, G. Maxwell & I. Savodnik - 1978 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 29 (1):61-68.
  • Treating connectionism properly: Reflections on Smolensky.Jay F. Rosenberg - 1990 - Psychological Research 52.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reductionism, levels of organization, and the mind-body problem.William C. Wimsatt - 1976 - In Gordon G. Globus (ed.), Consciousness and the Brain. Plenum Press.
  • Levels indeed! A response to Broadbent.J. L. McClelland & D. E. Rumelhart - 1985 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 114:193-7.
  • A question of levels: Comment on McClelland and rumelhart.D. Broadbent - 1985 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 114:189-92.