Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A Note on Berkeley's Corpuscularian Theories in "Siris".Gabriel Moked - 1971 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 2 (3):257.
  • Berkeley and the Microworld.Catherine Wilson - 1994 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 76 (1):37-64.
  • Action, knowledge and embodiment in Berkeley and Locke.Tom Stoneham - 2018 - Philosophical Explorations 21 (1):41-59.
    Embodiment is a fact of human existence which philosophers should not ignore. They may differ to a great extent in what they have to say about our bodies, but they have to take into account that for each of us our body has a special status, it is not merely one amongst the physical objects, but a physical object to which we have a unique relation. While Descartes approached the issue of embodiment through consideration of sensation and imagination, it is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Occasionalism and mechanism: Fontenelle's objections to Malebranche.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2008 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 16 (2):293 – 313.
    It is well known that the French Cartesian Nicolas Malebranche (1638–1715) was both an occasionalist in metaphysics and a mechanist in physics. He consistently argued that God is the only true caus...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Berkeley’s Best System: An Alternative Approach to Laws of Nature.Walter Ott - 2019 - Journal of Modern Philosophy 1 (1):4.
    Contemporary Humeans treat laws of nature as statements of exceptionless regularities that function as the axioms of the best deductive system. Such ‘Best System Accounts’ marry realism about laws with a denial of necessary connections among events. I argue that Hume’s predecessor, George Berkeley, offers a more sophisticated conception of laws, equally consistent with the absence of powers or necessary connections among events in the natural world. On this view, laws are not statements of regularities but the most general rules (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Metaphysics and the philosophy of science.Gerd Buchdahl - 1969 - Oxford,: Blackwell.
  • Language and the Structure of Berkeley's World.Kenneth L. Pearce - 2017 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Berkeley's philosophy is meant to be a defense of commonsense. However, Berkeley's claim that the ultimate constituents of physical reality are fleeting, causally passive ideas appears to be radically at odds with commonsense. In particular, such a theory seems unable to account for the robust structure which commonsense (and Newtonian physics) takes the world to exhibit. The problem of structure, as I understand it, includes the problem of how qualities can be grouped by their co-occurrence in a single enduring object (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Berkeley.Lisa Downing - 2014 - Routledge.
  • Berkeley's philosophy of science.Richard J. Brook - 1973 - The Hague,: M. Nijhoff.
    INTRODUCTION Philonous: You see, Hylas, the water of yonder fountain, how it is forced upwards, in a round column, to a certain height, at which it breaks ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Principia: Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy.Isaac Newton - 1999 - University of California Press.
    Presents Newton's unifying idea of gravitation and explains how he converted physics from a science of explanation into a general mathematical system.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   191 citations  
  • Particles And Ideas: Bishop Berkeley's Corpuscularian Philosophy.Gabriel Moked - 1988 - New York: Clarendon Press.
    Demonstrating that in George Berkeley's last major work, Siris, Berkeley had converted to a belief in the usefulness of the concept and existence of minute particles, Moked here posits that Berkeley developed a highly original brand of corpuscularian physics.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Berkeley's Metaphysical Instrumentalism.Marc A. Hight - 2010 - In Silvia Parigi (ed.), George Berkeley: Science and Religion in the Age of Enlightenment. Springer.
  • Locke, Berkeley, and Corpuscular Scepticism.Daniel Garber - 1982 - In Colin Murray Turbayne (ed.), Berkeley: Critical and Interpretive Essays. University of Minnesota Press.
  • Berkeley and Newton on Gravity in Siris.Timo Airaksinen - 2010 - In Silvia Parigi (ed.), George Berkeley: Religion and Science in the Age of Enlightenment. Springer.
  • Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Science. The Classical Origins — Descartes to Kant.Gerd Buchdahl - 1969 - Studia Leibnitiana 3 (3):224-227.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Particles and Ideas, Bishop Berkeley's Corpuscularian Philosophy.Gabriel Moked - 1989 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 179 (4):599-600.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Language and the Structure of Berkeley's World.Kenneth L. Pearce - 2014 - Dissertation, University of Southern California
    Berkeley's philosophy is meant to be a defense of commonsense. However, Berkeley's claim that the ultimate constituents of physical reality are fleeting, causally passive ideas appears to be radically at odds with commonsense. In particular, such a theory seems unable to account for the robust structure which commonsense (and Newtonian physics) takes the world to exhibit. The problem of structure, as I understand it, includes the problem of how qualities can be grouped by their co-occurrence in a single enduring object (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • “Let the Occult Quality Go”: Interpreting Berkley's Metaphysics of Science.Tom Stoneham & Angelo Cei - 2009 - European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 5 (1):73 - 91.