Switch to: Citations

References in:

Kant's transcendental imagination

New York: Palgrave-Macmillan (2005)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Kant on causation: on the fivefold routes to the principle of causation.Steven M. Bayne - 2004 - Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
    A volume in the SUNY series in Philosophy George R. Lucas Jr., editor.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Kant on Causation: On the Fivefold Routes to the Principle of Causation.Steven M. Bayne - 2003 - Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
    _An in-depth examination of the nature of Kant's causal principle._.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Kant's theory of knowledge.Graham Bird - 1962 - New York,: Humanities Press.
  • Theoretical Philosophy, 1755–1770.David Walford (ed.) - 1992 - Cambridge University Press.
    This is the first volume of the first ever comprehensive edition of the works of Immanuel Kant in English translation. The eleven essays in this volume constitute Kant's theoretical, pre-critical philosophical writings from 1755 to 1770. Several of these pieces have never been translated into English before; others have long been unavailable in English. We can trace in these works the development of Kant's thought to the eventual emergence in 1770 of the two chief tenets of his mature philosophy: the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A Treatise of Human Nature.David Hume & A. D. Lindsay - 1969 - Harmondsworth,: Penguin Books. Edited by Ernest Campbell Mossner.
    One of Hume's most well-known works and a masterpiece of philosophy, A Treatise of Human Nature is indubitably worth taking the time to read.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   943 citations  
  • Heidegger’s Interpretation of Kant: Categories, Imagination and Temporality.M. Weatherston - 2002 - London, England: Springer.
    Is there any justification for Heidegger's famous 'violence' against Kant's philosophy? An independent assessment of the worth of Heidegger's argument is also made all the more pertinent by the evident misgivings Heidegger had about his interpretation of Kant. We must ask of Heidegger's interpretation of Kant: 1) Is this good Kant? and 2) Is this good Heidegger?
  • Concepts and Schematism.G. J. Warnock - 1948 - Analysis 9 (5):77 - 82.
  • A reply to mr. Sellars.P. F. Strawson - 1954 - Philosophical Review 63 (2):216-231.
  • On the logic of complex particulars.Wilfrid Sellars - 1949 - Mind 58 (231):306-338.
  • Particulars.Wilfrid Sellars - 1952 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 13 (2):184-199.
  • The philosophy of the young Kant: the precritical project.Martin Schönfeld - 2000 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This intellectual biography of Immanuel Kant's early years--from 1747 when his first book was published, to 1770 when his Critique of Pure Reason was about to be printed--makes an outstanding contribution to Kant scholarship. Schonfeld meticulously examines almost all of Kant's early works, summarizes their content, and exhibits their shortcomings and strengths. He places the early theories in their historical context and describes the scientific discoveries and philosophical innovations that distinguish Kant's pre-critical works. Schonfeld argues that these works were all (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • What is a thing?Martin Heidegger - 1967 - Lanham [Md.]: University Press of America. Edited by Eugene T. Gendlin.
  • Reply to Lorne Falkenstein.Rae Langton - 2001 - Kantian Review 5:64-72.
    In Kantian Humility I argue that, for Kant, ignorance of things in themselves is ignorance of the intrinsic properties of substances, and that this is epistemic humility, rather than idealism: some aspects of reality, the intrinsic aspects, are beyond our epistemic grasp.The interpretation draws upon what Falkenstein takes to be ‘a novel and not implausible understanding of Kant's distinction between things in themselves and appearances’ which views it as a distinction between the intrinsic and the relational. He concedes that Kant (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Kant on self-consciousness.Patricia Kitcher - 1999 - Philosophical Review 108 (3):345-386.
    The highest principle of Kant’s theoretical philosophy is that all cognition must “be combined in one single self-consciousness”. Elsewhere I have tried to explain why he believed that all cognition must belong to a single self ; here I try to clarify the other half of the doctrine. What led him to the claim that all cognition involved self-consciousness? This question is pressing, because the thesis strikes many as obviously false.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Connecting intuitions and concepts at B 160n.Patricia Kitcher - 1987 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 25 (S1):137-149.
  • Kritik der reinen Vernunft.Immanuel Kant - 2020 - Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG.
    überall einen richtigen Gebrauch der reinen Vernunft giebt, in welchem Fall es auch einen Canon derselben geben muß, so wird dieser nicht den speculativen, sondernden pr.ntischen Vernunftgebrauch betreffen, den wir also iezt ...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   632 citations  
  • A Treatise of Human Nature.David Hume & A. D. Lindsay - 1958 - Philosophical Quarterly 8 (33):379-380.
  • Visual geometry.James Hopkins - 1973 - Philosophical Review 82 (1):3-34.
    We cannot imagine two straight lines intersecting at two points even though they may do so. In this case our abilities to imagine depend upon our abilities to visualise.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Kant on the Mathematical Method.Jaakko Hintikka - 1967 - The Monist 51 (3):352-375.
    According to Kant, “mathematical knowledge is the knowledge gained by reason from the construction of concepts.” In this paper, I shall make a few suggestions as to how this characterization of the mathematical method is to be understood.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Review: C. F. v. Weizsacker, Komplementaritat und Logik. [REVIEW]Carl G. Hempel - 1958 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 23 (1):65-66.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Plato on Parts and Wholes: The Metaphysics of Structure.Verity Harte - 2002 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    What is the relation between a whole and its parts? The metaphysics of structure and composition is much discussed in modern philosophy; now Verity Harte provides the first sustained examination of Plato's rich but neglected discussion of the topic, and shows how it can illuminate current debates. This book is an invaluable resource both for scholars of Plato and for modern metaphysicians.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • The Failure of the B‐Deduction.Paul Guyer - 1987 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 25 (S1):67-84.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Particulars--bare and qualified.William P. Alston - 1954 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 15 (2):253-258.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Theoretical Philosophy After 1781.Henry E. Allison, Peter Heath, Gary Hatfield & Michael Friedman (eds.) - 2010 - Cambridge University Press.
    This volume, originally published in 2002, assembles the historical sequence of writings that Kant published between 1783 and 1796 to popularize, summarize, amplify and defend the doctrines of his masterpiece, the Critique of Pure Reason of 1781. The best known of them, the Prolegomena, is often recommended to beginning students, but the other texts are also vintage Kant and are important sources for a fully rounded picture of Kant's intellectual development. As with other volumes in the series there are copious (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Mathematics in Kant's Critical Philosophy.Emily Carson & Lisa Shabel (eds.) - 2015 - Routledge.
    There is a long tradition, in the history and philosophy of science, of studying Kant’s philosophy of mathematics, but recently philosophers have begun to examine the way in which Kant’s reflections on mathematics play a role in his philosophy more generally, and in its development. For example, in the Critique of Pure Reason , Kant outlines the method of philosophy in general by contrasting it with the method of mathematics; in the Critique of Practical Reason , Kant compares the Formula (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The structure of experience: Kant's system of principles.Gordon Nagel - 1983 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Kant and the exact sciences.Michael Friedman - 1992 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    In this new book, Michael Friedman argues that Kant's continuing efforts to find a metaphysics that could provide a foundation for the sciences is of the utmost ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   246 citations  
  • The Reception of Kant's Critical Philosophy: Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel.Sally S. Sedgwick (ed.) - 2000 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    The period from Kant to Hegel is one of the most intense and rigorous in modern philosophy. The central problem at the heart of it was the development of a new standard of theoretical reflection and of the principle of rationality itself. The essays in this volume, published in 2000, consider both the development of Kant's system of transcendental idealism in the three Critiques, the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science, and the Opus Postumum, as well as the reception and transformation (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Nature of Universals and Propositions.George Frederick Stout - 1921 - London,: Published for the British Academy by Oxford University Press.
  • Idealism as Modernism: Hegelian Variations.Robert B. Pippin - 1997 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    'Modernity' has come to refer both to a contested historical category and to an even more contested philosophical and civilisational ideal. In this important collection of essays Robert Pippin takes issue with some prominent assessments of what is or is not philosophically at stake in the idea of a modern revolution in Western civilisation, and presents an alternative view. Professor Pippin disputes many traditional characterisations of the distinctiveness of modern philosophy. In their place he defends claims about agency, freedom, ethical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Monadology.Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz - 1991 - Routledge. Edited by N. Rescher.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • Kant’s Account of Intuition.Lorne Falkenstein - 1991 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21 (2):165-193.
    This paper outlines the history of the distinction between a higher and a lower cognitive function up to Kant. It is argued that Kant initially drew the distinction in Scholastic terms--as a distinction between a capacity to image particulars and a capacity to represent universals. However, features of his project in the Critique led him to reformulate the distinction in terms of immediacy and mediacy. Nonetheless, for certain purposes the older, Scholastic distinction retained its attractiveness, and this is the ground (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Proof-Structure of Kant's Transcendental Deduction.Dieter Henrich - 1969 - Review of Metaphysics 22 (4):640-659.
    Hence, there is still controversy over which of the two versions of the deduction deserves priority and whether indeed any distinction between them can be maintained that would go beyond questions of presentation and involve the structure of the proof itself. Schopenhauer and Heidegger held that the first edition alone fully expresses Kant's unique philosophy, while Kant himself, as well as many other Kantians, have only seen a difference in the method of presentation.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Having the world in view: Sellars, Kant, and intentionality.John Mcdowell - 1998 - Journal of Philosophy 95 (9):431-492.
  • Kant's Model of the Mind.Wayne Allan Waxman - 1987 - Dissertation, University of California, Santa Barbara
    The central thesis is that Kant's account of possible experience is actually an extension and development of an independent, prior theory of the possibility of perception. Since no school of Kant commentary acknowledges any such strict separation of problematics, its espousal poses the challenge of not simply refuting prevailing views but also defining a new alternative, i.e. a hitherto neglected body of doctrine not part of but premise to Kant's theory of experience. ;To meet this challenge, Kant's theory of the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Kantian Humility.Rae Langton - 1995 - Dissertation, Princeton University
    The distinction at the heart of Kant's philosophy is a metaphysical distinction: things in themselves are substances, bearers of intrinsic properties; phenomena are relational properties of substances. Kant says that things as we know them are composed "entirely of relations", by which he means forces. Kant's claim that we have no knowledge of things in themselves is not idealism, but humility: we have no knowledge of the intrinsic properties of substances. Kant has an empiricist starting-point. Human beings are receptive creatures. (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • Kant.Eric Watkins - 2009 - In Helen Beebee, Christopher Hitchcock & Peter Menzies (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Causation. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Subject and Predicate in Logic and Grammar.P. F. Strawson - 1974 - Philosophy 50 (194):481-483.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Subject and Predicate in Logic and Grammar.P. F. Strawson - 1974 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 38 (2):322-322.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Imagination and perception.P. F. Strawson - 1982 - In Ralph Charles Sutherland Walker (ed.), Kant on Pure Reason. Oxford University Press.
  • Psychological Studies in the Elements of Logic.Edmund G. Husserl - 1977 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 58 (4):297.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations