Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Simplicii in Aristotelis Physicorum Libros Quattuor Priores Commentaria.Hermann Simplicius, Michael Diels & Hayduck - 1960 - Legare Street Press.
    This work has been selected by scholars as being culturally important, and is part of the knowledge base of civilization as we know it. This work is in the "public domain in the United States of America, and possibly other nations. Within the United States, you may freely copy and distribute this work, as no entity (individual or corporate) has a copyright on the body of the work. Scholars believe, and we concur, that this work is important enough to be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Is There a Problem About Substitutional Quantification?Saul A. Kripke - 1976 - In Gareth Evans & John Henry McDowell (eds.), Truth and meaning: essays in semantics. Oxford [Eng.]: Clarendon Press. pp. 324-419.
  • Collected papers.Charles S. Peirce - 1931 - Cambridge,: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
    v. 1-2. Principles of philosophy and Elements of logic.--v. 3-4. Exact logic (published papers) and The simplest mathematics.--v. 5-6. Pragmatism and pragmaticism and Scientific metaphysics.--v. 7. Science and philosophy.--v. 8. Reviews, correspondence and bibliography.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   266 citations  
  • The Shaping of Deduction in Greek Mathematics: A Study in Cognitive History.Reviel Netz - 1999 - Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.
    An examination of the emergence of the phenomenon of deductive argument in classical Greek mathematics.
  • .E. Hussey (ed.) - 1973 - Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Note Textuelle sur un (Problème de) Lieu Géométrique dans les Météorologiques d'Aristote (III. 5, 375 b 16 – 376 b 22).Bernard Vitrac - 2002 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 56 (3):239-283.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Decision Method for Elementary Algebra and Geometry.Alfred Tarski - 1952 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 17 (3):207-207.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • A Decision Method for Elementary Algebra and Geometry.Alfred Tarski - 1949 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 14 (3):188-188.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • What Is Aristotelian Ecthesis?Robin Smith - 1982 - History and Philosophy of Logic 3 (2):113-127.
    I consider the proper interpretation of the process of ecthesis which Aristotle uses several times in the Prior analytics for completing a syllogistic mood, i.e., showing how to produce a deduction of a conclusion of a certain form from premisses of certain forms. I consider two interpretations of the process which have been advocated by recent scholars and show that one seems better suited to most passages while the other best fits a single remaining passage. I also argue that ecthesis (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Uses of construction in problems and theorems in Euclid’s Elements I–VI.Nathan Sidoli - 2018 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 72 (4):403-452.
    In this paper, I present an interpretation of the use of constructions in both the problems and theorems of Elements I–VI, in light of the concept of given as developed in the Data, that makes a distinction between the way that constructions are used in problems, problem-constructions, and the way that they are used in theorems and in the proofs of problems, proof-constructions. I begin by showing that the general structure of a problem is slightly different from that stated by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Mathematical Logic as Based on the Theory of Types.Bertrand Russell - 1908 - American Journal of Mathematics 30 (3):222-262.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   278 citations  
  • Sur La Valeur Fondamentale De : Une Réplique.C. J. Ruijgh - 1984 - Mnemosyne 37 (3-4):264-270.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The twofold role of diagrams in Euclid’s plane geometry.Marco Panza - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):55-102.
    Proposition I.1 is, by far, the most popular example used to justify the thesis that many of Euclid’s geometric arguments are diagram-based. Many scholars have recently articulated this thesis in different ways and argued for it. My purpose is to reformulate it in a quite general way, by describing what I take to be the twofold role that diagrams play in Euclid’s plane geometry (EPG). Euclid’s arguments are object-dependent. They are about geometric objects. Hence, they cannot be diagram-based unless diagrams (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Axiomatizing geometric constructions.Victor Pambuccian - 2008 - Journal of Applied Logic 6 (1):24-46.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Proofs, pictures, and Euclid.John Mumma - 2010 - Synthese 175 (2):255 - 287.
    Though pictures are often used to present mathematical arguments, they are not typically thought to be an acceptable means for presenting mathematical arguments rigorously. With respect to the proofs in the Elements in particular, the received view is that Euclid's reliance on geometric diagrams undermines his efforts to develop a gap-free deductive theory. The central difficulty concerns the generality of the theory. How can inferences made from a particular diagrams license general mathematical results? After surveying the history behind the received (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Deductive Structure of Euclid 's "Elements".Michael Boylan - 1983 - Philosophy of Science 50 (4):665-668.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Philosophy of mathematics and deductive structure in Euclid's Elements.Ian Mueller - 1981 - Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications.
    A survey of Euclid's Elements, this text provides an understanding of the classical Greek conception of mathematics and its similarities to modern views as well as its differences. It focuses on philosophical, foundational, and logical questions — rather than strictly historical and mathematical issues — and features several helpful appendixes.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Aristotle on Geometrical Objects.Ian Mueller - 1970 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 52 (2):156-171.
  • Tῷ vs tῶν in Prior Analytics 1.1–22.Marko Malink - 2008 - Classical Quarterly 58 (2):519-.
  • Aristotle on Principles as Elements.Marko Malink - 2017 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 53.
  • Reasoning with Arbitrary Objects.John Macnamara - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (1):305.
  • Beginning Logic.Sarah Stebbins - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (2):421-423.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Beginning Logic.Sarah Stebbins - 1965 - London, England: Hackett Publishing.
    "One of the most careful and intensive among the introductory texts that can be used with a wide range of students. It builds remarkably sophisticated technical skills, a good sense of the nature of a formal system, and a solid and extensive background for more advanced work in logic.... The emphasis throughout is on natural deduction derivations, and the text's deductive systems are its greatest strength. Lemmon's unusual procedure of presenting derivations before truth tables is very effective." --Sarah Stebbins, The (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • Geometrical Method and Aristotle's Account of First Principles.H. D. P. Lee - 1935 - Classical Quarterly 29 (02):113-.
    The object of this paper is to show the predominance of the influence of geometrical ideas in Aristotle's account of first principles in the Posterior Analytics— to show that his analysis of first principles is in its essentials an analysis of the first principles of geometry as he conceived them. My proof of this falls into two parts. I. A consideration of the parallel between Aristotle's and Euclid's account of first principles. II. A comparison between the general movement of thought (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Geometrical Method and Aristotle's Account of First Principles.H. D. P. Lee - 1935 - Classical Quarterly 29 (2):113-124.
    The object of this paper is to show the predominance of the influence of geometrical ideas in Aristotle's account of first principles in the Posterior Analytics— to show that his analysis of first principles is in its essentials an analysis of the first principles of geometry as he conceived them. My proof of this falls into two parts. I. A consideration of the parallel between Aristotle's and Euclid's account of first principles. II. A comparison between the general movement of thought (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Instantial terms, anaphora and arbitrary objects.Jeffrey C. King - 1991 - Philosophical Studies 61 (3):239 - 265.
  • Kritik der reinen Vernunft.Immanuel Kant - 2020 - Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG.
    überall einen richtigen Gebrauch der reinen Vernunft giebt, in welchem Fall es auch einen Canon derselben geben muß, so wird dieser nicht den speculativen, sondernden pr.ntischen Vernunftgebrauch betreffen, den wir also iezt ...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   632 citations  
  • Logische Untersuchungen: Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis.Edmund Husserl (ed.) - 1993 - Tübingen,: de Gruyter.
    Husserls »Logische Untersuchungen« sind eines der folgenreichsten Werke der neueren Philosophiegeschichte. Mit dem ersten Erscheinen in den Jahren 1900 und 1901 (Max Niemeyer Verlag, Halle/Saale) nimmt jene Schule ihren Anfang, deren Name im Untertitel des zweiten Bandes zum ersten Mal sinnfällig wird: die Phänomenologie. Husserl sah damals in diesem Werk »Versuche zur Neubegründung der reinen Logik und Erkenntnistheorie«, die den Grund zu einem größeren Gedankengebäude zu legen imstande waren. Sie wollten freilich kein bloßes Programm sein, sondern »Fundamentalarbeit an den unmittelbar (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   430 citations  
  • Mathematics in Aristotle.Thomas Heath - 1949 - Philosophy 24 (91):348-349.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Mathematics in Aristotle.Thomas Heath - 1949 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 57 (4):458-459.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Mathematics in Aristotle.Thomas Heath - 1949 - Routledge.
    Originally published in 1949. This meticulously researched book presents a comprehensive outline and discussion of Aristotle’s mathematics with the author's translations of the greek. To Aristotle, mathematics was one of the three theoretical sciences, the others being theology and the philosophy of nature. Arranged thematically, this book considers his thinking in relation to the other sciences and looks into such specifics as squaring of the circle, syllogism, parallels, incommensurability of the diagonal, angles, universal proof, gnomons, infinity, agelessness of the universe, (...)
  • Reasoning with arbitrary objects.Kit Fine - 1985 - New York, NY, USA: Blackwell.
    Contents: Preface VII; Introduction 1; 1. The General Framework 5; 2. Some Standard Systems 61; 3. Systems in General 147; 4. Non-Standard Systems 177; Bibliography 210; General Index 215; Index of Symbols 219-220.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Reasoning with Arbitrary Objects.Marco Santambrogio - 1988 - Noûs 22 (4):630-635.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • A Defence of Arbitrary Objects.Kit Fine & Neil Tennant - 1983 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 57 (1):55 - 89.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • The Stoics on Hypotheses and Hypothetical Arguments.Susanne Bobzien - 1997 - Phronesis 42 (3):299-312.
    ABSTRACT: In this paper I argue (i) that the hypothetical arguments about which the Stoic Chrysippus wrote numerous books (DL 7.196) are not to be confused with the so-called hypothetical syllogisms" but are the same hypothetical arguments as those mentioned five times in Epictetus (e.g. Diss. 1.25.11-12); and (ii) that these hypothetical arguments are formed by replacing in a non-hypothetical argument one (or more) of the premisses by a Stoic "hypothesis" or supposition. Such "hypotheses" or suppositions differ from propositions in (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Über lockes „allgemeines dreieck”.Evert Willem Beth - 1956 - Kant Studien 48 (1-4):361-380.
  • Osservazioni sull’uso delle lettere nella sillogistica di Aristotele.Jonathan Barnes - 2006 - Elenchos 27 (2):277-304.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Osservazioni sull’uso delle lettere nella sillogistica di Aristotele.Jonathan Barnes - 2006 - Elenchos 27 (2):277-304.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A formal system for euclid’s elements.Jeremy Avigad, Edward Dean & John Mumma - 2009 - Review of Symbolic Logic 2 (4):700--768.
    We present a formal system, E, which provides a faithful model of the proofs in Euclid's Elements, including the use of diagrammatic reasoning.
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Aristotle and euclid's postulates.Fabio Acerbi - 2013 - Classical Quarterly 63 (2):680-685.
    Book 1 of Euclid's Elements opens with a set of unproved assumptions: definitions, postulates, and ‘common notions’. The common notions are general rules validating deductions that involve the relations of equality and congruence. The attested postulates are five in number, even if a part of the manuscript tradition adds a sixth, almost surely spurious, that in some manuscripts features as the ninth, and last, common notion. The postulates are called αἰτήματα both in the manuscripts of the Elements and in the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Logic, language-games and information: Kantian themes in the philosophy of logic.Jaakko Hintikka - 1973 - Oxford,: Clarendon Press.
    I LOGIC IN PHILOSOPHY— PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC i. On the relation of logic to philosophy I n this book, the consequences of certain logical insights for ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. To Which Are Now Added, I. Analysis of Mr. Locke's Doctrine of Ideas [&C.].John Locke - 1818
  • Syllabus of a Proposed System of Logic.Augustus de Morgan - 1860 - London, England: Walton & Maberly.
  • .E. J. Lemmon - 1966
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Aristotle and Logical Theory.Jonathan Lear - 1980 - Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
    Aristotle was the first and one of the greatest logicians. He not only devised the first system of formal logic, but also raised many fundamental problems in the philosophy of logic. In this book, Dr Lear shows how Aristotle's discussion of logical consequence, validity and proof can contribute to contemporary debates in the philosophy of logic. No background knowledge of Aristotle is assumed.
  • Principles of Human Knowledge: And, Three Dialogues.George Berkeley - 1988 - Oxford: Oxford University Press. Edited by Howard Robinson & George Berkeley.
    Berkeley's idealism started a revolution in philosophy. As one of the great empiricist thinkers he not only influenced British philosphers from Hume to Russell and the logical positivists in the twentieth-century, he also set the scene for the continental idealism of Hegel and even the philosophy of Marx. This edition of Berkeley's two key works has an introduction which examines and in part defends his arguments for idealism, as well as offering a detailed analytical contents list, extensive philosophical notes, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Hypotheses and the Euclidean Postulates.Alfonso Gómez-Lobo - 1977 - Review of Metaphysics 30 (3):430 - 439.
    I would like to challenge this view on various grounds, but before I do so, I wish to provide a broader setting for the problems discussed in this paper.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Verb ‘Be’ in Ancient Greek (Reprint with a New Introductory Essay).C. H. Kahn - unknown
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Reasoning with Arbitrary Objects.Kit Fine - 1985 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 176 (3):402-403.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • Diagram-Based Geometric Practice.Kenneth Manders - 2008 - In Paolo Mancosu (ed.), The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Oxford University Press. pp. 65--79.
    This chapter provides a survey of issues about diagrams in traditional geometrical reasoning. After briefly refuting several common philosophical objections, and giving a sketch of diagram-based reasoning practice in Euclidean plane geometry, discussion focuses first on problems of diagram sensitivity, and then on the relationship between uniform treatment and geometrical generality. Here, one finds a balance between representationally enforced unresponsiveness (to differences among diagrams) and the intellectual agent's contribution to such unresponsiveness that is somewhat different from what one has come (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations