How Archaeological Evidence Bites Back: Strategies for Putting Old Data to Work in New Ways

Science, Technology, and Human Values 42 (2):203-225 (2017)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Archaeological data are shadowy in a number of senses. Not only are they notoriously fragmentary but the conceptual and technical scaffolding on which archaeologists rely to constitute these data as evidence can be as constraining as it is enabling. A recurrent theme in internal archaeological debate is that reliance on sedimented layers of interpretative scaffolding carries the risk that “preunderstandings” configure what archaeologists recognize and record as primary data, and how they interpret it as evidence. The selective and destructive nature of data capture in archeology further suggests that there may be little scope for putting “legacy” data to work in new ways. And yet archaeologists have been strikingly successful in mining old datasets for new insights. I situate these concerns in the broader context of debate about the epistemic standing of the historical sciences, and then consider three strategies by which archaeologists address the challenges posed by legacy data. The first two – secondary retrieval and recontextualization – are a matter of reconfiguring the scaffolding that underpins evidential reasoning. The third turns on redeploying old data in the context of computational models that support the experimental simulation of the cultural systems and contexts under study.

Links

PhilArchive

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Evidential Reasoning in Archaeology.Robert Chapman & Alison Wylie - 2016 - London: Bloomsbury Academic Publishing.
Material Evidence.Alison Wylie & Robert Chapman (eds.) - 2014 - New York / London: Routledge.
Critical distance : stabilising evidential claims in archaeology.Alison Wylie - 2011 - In Philip Dawid, William Twining & Mimi Vasilaki (eds.), Evidence, Inference and Enquiry. Oup/British Academy.
Data models and the acquisition and manipulation of data.Todd Harris - 2003 - Philosophy of Science 70 (5):1508-1517.
The Analysis of Data and the Evidential Scope of Neuroimaging Results.Jessey Wright - 2018 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 69 (4):1179-1203.
Theory, Locality, and Methodology in Archaeology: Just add water?William H. Krieger - 2012 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 2 (2):243-257.
Data, phenomena, and reliability.James Woodward - 2000 - Philosophy of Science 67 (3):179.
Ethics and Epistemology of Big Data.Ian Kerridge, Paul H. Mason & Wendy Lipworth - 2017 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 14 (4):485-488.
Evidence in Neuroimaging: Towards a Philosophy of Data Analysis.Jessey Wright - 2017 - Dissertation, The University of Western Ontario
The Effects of Fraud on the Evaluation of Health Care.Paul Jesilow - 2005 - Health Care Analysis 13 (3):239-245.
Confirmation, Refutation, and the Evidence of fMRI.Christopher Mole & Colin Klein - 2010 - In Stephen Hanson & Martin Bunzl (eds.), Foundational Issues in Human Brain Mapping. Cambridge: MIT Press. pp. 99.
Positivism and the New Archaeology.Margaret Alison Wylie - 1982 - Dissertation, State University of New York at Binghamton

Analytics

Added to PP
2018-01-12

Downloads
547 (#31,764)

6 months
116 (#31,190)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Alison Wylie
University of British Columbia

References found in this work

The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1962 - Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Edited by Ian Hacking.
The Uses of Argument.Stephen E. Toulmin - 1958 - Philosophy 34 (130):244-245.
Patterns of Discovery.Norwood R. Hanson, A. D. Ritchie & Henryk Mehlberg - 1960 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 10 (40):346-349.

View all 27 references / Add more references