The Sting of Intentional Pain

Abstract

When someone steps on your toe on purpose, it seems to hurt more than when the person does the same thing unintentionally. The physical parameters of the harm may not differ—your toe is flattened in both cases—but the psychological experience of pain is changed nonetheless. Intentional harms are premeditated by another person and have the specific purpose of causing pain. In a sense, intended harms are events initiated by one mind to communicate meaning (malice) to another, and this could shape the recipient’s experience. This study examined whether self-reported pain is indeed higher when the events producing the pain are understood as intentionally (as opposed to unintentionally) caused by another person. Although pain was traditionally conceived to be solely physical in nature (Aydede, 2005), its experience varies substantially with psychological context. The placebo analgesia effect, for example, is the reduction of pain without a change in physical stimulation when context, expectations, or sugar pills challenge the interpretation of a sensation as painful (e.g., Fields, 2008). The nocebo effect, in turn, is the experience of pain without any physical stimulation—as when participants report headaches when told that a (nonexistent) electric current is passing through their heads (Schweiger & Parducci, 1981). These variations in pain experience seem to depend on the meaning of the stimulus: A sugar pill is meant to decrease pain, whereas electric current is meant to increase pain. In an interpersonal context, the meaning of an action is derived from the would complete. perceiver’s perceptions of the actor’s intention (Clark, 1996).

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,349

External links

  • This entry has no external links. Add one.
Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

  • Only published works are available at libraries.

Similar books and articles

The Intentional Structure of Consciousness.Tim Crane - 2002 - In Aleksandar Jokic & Quentin Smith (eds.), Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 33-56.
Do animals feel pain?Peter Singer - 1990 - In Peter. Singer (ed.), Animal Liberation. Avon Books.
Pain perception, affective mechanisms, and conscious experience.C. Richard Chapman - 2004 - In Thomas Hadjistavropoulos & Kenneth D. Craig (eds.), Pain: Psychological Perspectives. pp. 59-85.
Pain, cortex, and consciousness.Marshall Devor - 2007 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (1):89-90.
Pain and folk theory.C. R. Chapman, Y. Nakakura & C. N. Chapman - 2000 - Brain and Mind 1 (2):209-222.
Distinguishing the Appearance from the Reality of Pain.Kevin Reuter - 2011 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 18 (9-10):94-109.
What is pain facial expression for?Nico H. Frijda - 2002 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25 (4):460-460.
Knowledge and pain.Esther Cohen (ed.) - 2012 - New York, NY: Rodopi.
Mad, Martian, but not mad Martian pain.Peter Alward - 2004 - Sorites 15 (December):73-75.
The pain problem.Terry Dartnall - 2001 - Philosophical Psychology 14 (1):95-102.
Objective and subjective aspects of pain.Nikola Grahek - 1991 - Philosophical Psychology 4 (2):249-66.

Analytics

Added to PP
2010-12-22

Downloads
34 (#456,993)

6 months
1 (#1,533,009)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?