Circular Motion and Circular Thought: A Synthetic Approach to the Fifth Element in Aristotle’s de Philosophia and de Caelo

Apeiron 56 (1):15-42 (2023)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Scholars have long considered de Philosophia and de Caelo to be in contradiction regarding the nature of the heavenly bodies, particularly with respect to the activity proper to the element composing them. According to the accounts we have of de Philosophia, Aristotle seems to have put forth that stars move because they have minds, and, according to Cicero’s account of the lost text, they choose their actions out of free will. In de Caelo, however, Aristotle seems only to consider that stars engage in the activity of circular motion because it is in their nature to do so, as it is in the nature of, e.g. fire to move upwards or Earth to move downwards. In this paper, I argue against the longstanding view that there is an incompatibility between these two “early” cosmological texts of Aristotle. I aim to show that these two texts endorse complementary, not contradictory, views of the heavenly bodies. I argue that in de Philosophia, Aristotle attributes to stars the intellective counterpart of the spatial motion which is developed in greater depth in de Caelo, while in de Caelo, we see hints of Aristotle’s view in de Philosophia that the stars are also minds and are able to rationally cognize their particular good – a point which is shown in de Caelo 292a18–293a14, where Aristotle attributes both life and praxis to the heavenly bodies. The overarching view which I present of these two texts is that while de Caelo approaches the heavenly bodies qua bodies and de Philosophia approaches them qua minds, they are still examining one and the same substance and that Aristotle has not changed his mind regarding the basic nature of such a substance in the (supposed) interim between writing de Philosophia and de Caelo. Rather, we find echoes of de Caelo in de Philosophia, and echoes of de Philosophia in de Caelo, which speaks to the fact that Aristotle maintains one view of the heavenly bodies which he presents over the course of these two texts.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,349

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Aristotle on Circular Proof.Marko Malink - 2013 - Phronesis 58 (3):215-248.
Descartes and Circular Inertia.Edward Slowik - 1999 - Modern Schoolman 77 (1):1-11.
Virtuous Circles.Aldo Antonelli - 2000 - In Anil Gupta & Andre Chapuis (eds.), Circularity, Definition, and Truth. Indian Council of Philosophical Research.
When is circularity in definitions benign?J. A. Burgess - 2007 - Philosophical Quarterly 58 (231):214–233.
Aristotle’s Great Clock.James Bogen & J. E. McGuire - 1986 - Philosophy Research Archives 12:387-448.
A Critique of Two Criteria of Epistemically Circular Belief.Todd M. Stewart - 2013 - Southwest Philosophy Review 29 (1):173-183.
The Tokenization of 'Zero' and 'One'.Ilexa Yardley - 2021 - Https://Medium.Com/the-Circular-Theory/.

Analytics

Added to PP
2021-11-19

Downloads
12 (#1,054,764)

6 months
3 (#1,023,809)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Aristotle’s Physics.W. D. Ross - 1936 - Philosophy 11 (43):352-354.
The Development of Aristotle's Theology—I.W. K. C. Guthrie - 1933 - Classical Quarterly 27 (3-4):162-.
L''me du monde de Platon aux Stoïciens.Joseph Moreau - 1940 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 47 (3):342-343.
Théologie cosmique et Théologie chrétienne.Jean Pépin - 1965 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 70 (1):114-116.

View all 9 references / Add more references