Do conjunctive forks always point to a common cause?

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (3):384-387 (1987)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

This article has no associated abstract. (fix it)

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 90,593

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Conjunctive forks and temporally asymmetric inference.Elliott Sober & Martin Barrett - 1992 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 70 (1):1 – 23.
A conjunction in closure spaces.Andrzej W. Jankowski - 1984 - Studia Logica 43 (4):341 - 351.
Metaphysical Arguments against Ordinary Objects.Amie L. Thomasson - 2006 - Philosophical Quarterly 56 (224):340 - 359.
Iterative and fixed point common belief.Aviad Heifetz - 1999 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 28 (1):61-79.
Not every truth can be known (at least, not all at once).Greg Restall - 2009 - In Joe Salerno (ed.), New Essays on the Knowability Paradox. Oxford University Press. pp. 339--354.
Causality: Production and Propagation.Wesley C. Salmon - 1980 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1980 (Volume Two: Symposia and Invited):49 - 69.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
90 (#174,199)

6 months
12 (#122,866)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

References found in this work

The sciences of the artificial.Herbert Alexander Simon - 1969 - [Cambridge,: M.I.T. Press.
The Direction of Time.Hans Reichenbach - 1956 - Philosophy 34 (128):65-66.
Objective knowledge, an evolutionary approach.Karl R. Popper - 1976 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 166 (1):72-73.
Review of T he Direction of Time.Henryk Mehlberg - 1962 - Philosophical Review 71 (1):99.
Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach.James A. Martin - 1975 - Philosophical Review 84 (1):103.

View all 8 references / Add more references