How People Judge What Is Reasonable

Alabama Law Review 70 (2):293-359 (2018)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

A classic debate concerns whether reasonableness should be understood statistically (e.g., reasonableness is what is common) or prescriptively (e.g., reasonableness is what is good). This Article elaborates and defends a third possibility. Reasonableness is a partly statistical and partly prescriptive “hybrid,” reflecting both statistical and prescriptive considerations. Experiments reveal that people apply reasonableness as a hybrid concept, and the Article argues that a hybrid account offers the best general theory of reasonableness. First, the Article investigates how ordinary people judge what is reasonable. Reasonableness sits at the core of countless legal standards, yet little work has investigated how ordinary people (i.e., potential jurors) actually make reasonableness judgments. Experiments reveal that judgments of reasonableness are systematically intermediate between judgments of the relevant average and ideal across numerous legal domains. For example, participants’ mean judgment of the legally reasonable number of weeks’ delay before a criminal trial (ten weeks) falls between the judged average (seventeen weeks) and ideal (seven weeks). So too for the reasonable num- ber of days to accept a contract offer, the reasonable rate of attorneys’ fees, the reasonable loan interest rate, and the reasonable annual number of loud events on a football field in a residential neighborhood. Judgment of reasonableness is better predicted by both statistical and prescriptive factors than by either factor alone. This Article uses this experimental discovery to develop a normative view of reasonableness. It elaborates an account of reasonableness as a hybrid standard, arguing that this view offers the best general theory of reasonableness, one that applies correctly across multiple legal domains. Moreover, this hybrid feature is the historical essence of legal reasonableness: the original use of the “reasonable person” and the “man on the Clapham omnibus” aimed to reflect both statistical and prescriptive considerations. Empirically, reasonableness is a hybrid judgment. And normatively, reasonableness should be applied as a hybrid standard.

Links

PhilArchive

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Reasonable women in the law.Susan Dimock - 2008 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 11 (2):153-175.
What is reasonableness?James W. Boettcher - 2004 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 30 (5-6):597-621.
Individualizing the Reasonable Person in Criminal Law.Peter Westen - 2008 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 2 (2):137-162.
Democratic reasonableness.Thomas A. Spragens - 2008 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 11 (2):193-214.
Against Personifying the Reasonable Person.Matt King - 2017 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 11 (4):725-732.
Reasonable Partiality in Professional Relationships.Brenda Almond - 2005 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 8 (1-2):155-168.
Reasonable Doubts About Reasonable Nonbelief.Douglas V. Henry - 2008 - Faith and Philosophy 25 (3):276-289.
Reasonableness and Fairness: A Historical Theory.Christopher McMahon - 2016 - Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press.
The place of unreasonable people beyond Rawls.Roberta Sala - 2013 - European Journal of Political Theory 12 (3):253-270.
Reasonable Self-Esteem.Richard Keshen - 2000 - Mind 109 (436):944-947.
Political liberalism: Reasonableness and democratic practice.Sebastiano Maffettone - 2004 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 30 (5-6):541-577.

Analytics

Added to PP
2018-11-07

Downloads
1,003 (#12,912)

6 months
118 (#30,298)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Kevin Tobia
Georgetown University

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references