Markets in Votes and the Tyranny of Wealth

Res Publica 23 (3):313-328 (2017)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

A standard objection to a market in political votes is that it will enable the rich politically to dominate the poor. If a market in votes was allowed then the poor would be the most likely sellers and the rich the most likely buyers. The rich would thus accumulate the votes of the poor, and so the candidates elected and the policies passed would represent only their interests and not those of the electorate as a whole. To ensure that the poor do not become de facto disenfranchised, then, markets in votes should be disallowed. This objection seems so straightforward and compelling that it has received almost no critical scrutiny. This is unfortunate, for close examination reveals that this argument is not as straightforward as it initially appears. Indeed, there are four different ways of understanding this objection. It could be understood as expressing: the concern that markets in votes would enable candidates to win elections who would otherwise lose them; the concern that they would enable the election of candidates opposed by the majority of the electorate; the concern that they would lead to the poor having disproportionately low political influence; and the concern that they would lead to the rich having disproportionately high political influence. I will argue in this paper that only and could plausibly ground objections to markets in votes. Moreover, these will only plausibly ground objections to unrestricted markets in votes; they will not ground objections to markets in votes per se. Thus, if we are to continue to object to markets in political votes we will have to do this on grounds other than that were they to be allowed the rich will politically dominate the poor.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,386

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Vote Markets.Christopher Freiman - 2014 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 92 (4):759-774.
Autonomy, Vote Buying, and Constraining Options.James Stacey Taylor - 2016 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 34 (5):711-723.
The Effect of Dual Candidacy on Voting Decisions.Yoichi Hizen - 2006 - Japanese Journal of Political Science 7 (3):289-306.
The myth of the rational voter?Donald Wittman - 2008 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 20 (3):359-375.
Rationalising discursive anomalies.Robert E. Goodin - 2009 - Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory 56 (119):1-13.

Analytics

Added to PP
2016-09-20

Downloads
40 (#389,966)

6 months
13 (#184,769)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

James Taylor
The College of New Jersey

References found in this work

Political Liberalism.John Rawls - 1993 - Columbia University Press.
Deliberative Democracy and the Discursive Dilemma.Philip Pettit - 2001 - Philosophical Issues 11 (1):268-299.
The Ethics of Voting.Jason Brennan - 2011 - Princeton Univ Pr.

View all 15 references / Add more references