Why Physicians Ought to Lie for Their Patients

American Journal of Bioethics 12 (3):4-12 (2012)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Sometimes physicians lie to third-party payers in order to grant their patients treatment they would otherwise not receive. This strategy, commonly known as gaming the system, is generally condemned for three reasons. First, it may hurt the patient for the sake of whom gaming was intended. Second, it may hurt other patients. Third, it offends contractual and distributive justice. Hence, gaming is considered to be immoral behavior. This article is an attempt to show that, on the contrary, gaming may sometimes be a physician's duty. Under specific circumstances, gaming may be necessary from the viewpoint of the internal morality of medicine. Moreover, the objections against gaming are examples of what we call the idealistic fallacy, that is, the fallacy of passing judgments in a nonideal world according to ideal standards. Hence, the objections are inconclusive. Gaming is sometimes justified, and may even be required in the name of beneficence

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,202

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

What doctors should call their patients.M. Lavin - 1988 - Journal of Medical Ethics 14 (3):129-131.
The patient's duty to adhere to prescribed treatment: An ethical analysis.David B. Resnik - 2005 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 30 (2):167 – 188.
Professional autonomy in belgium.Herman Nys & Paul Schotsmans - 2000 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 21 (5):425-439.
The art of videogames.Grant Tavinor - 2009 - Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
Patient autonomy, paternalism, and the conscientious physician.Stephen Wear - 1983 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 4 (3).
The real problem with equipoise.Winston Chiong - 2006 - American Journal of Bioethics 6 (4):37 – 47.
Gaming the transplant system.Timothy F. Murphy - 2004 - American Journal of Bioethics 4 (1):28.
The concept of medically indicated treatment.Franklin G. Miller - 1993 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 18 (1):91-98.

Analytics

Added to PP
2012-03-15

Downloads
62 (#250,399)

6 months
10 (#219,185)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Samia Hurst
University of Geneva

Citations of this work

Deception and the Clinical Ethicist.Christopher Meyers - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):4-12.
Rationing conscience.Dominic Wilkinson - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (4):226-229.
Ethics of psychotherapist deception.Drew A. Curtis & Leslie J. Kelley - 2020 - Ethics and Behavior 30 (8):601-616.
Why Physicians Should Not Lie for Their Patients.Robert M. Sade - 2012 - American Journal of Bioethics 12 (3):17-19.

View all 12 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

The Right and the Good. Some Problems in Ethics.W. D. Ross - 1930 - Oxford: Clarendon Press. Edited by Philip Stratton-Lake.
After Virtue.A. MacIntyre - 1981 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 46 (1):169-171.
Just Health: Meeting Health Needs Fairly.Norman Daniels - 2007 - Cambridge University Press.
The Right and the Good.David Ross - 1930 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK. Edited by Philip Stratton-Lake.
Ideal Theory in Theory and Practice.Ingrid Robeyns - 2008 - Social Theory and Practice 34 (3):341-362.

View all 22 references / Add more references