Meaning, Interpretation

In D. Beaver & P. Scotto di Luzio (eds.), Words, Proofs, and Diagrams. CSLI Publications. pp. 217-240 (2002)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

This paper1 explores, quite tentatively, possible consequences for the concept of semantics of two phenomena concerning meaning and interpretation, viz., radical interpretation and normativity of meaning. Both, it will be argued, challenge the way in which meaning is conceived of in semantics and thereby the status of the discipline itself. For several reasons it seems opportune to explore these issues. If one reviews the developments in semantics over the past two decades, one observes that quite a bit has changed, and one may well wonder how to assess these changes. This relates directly to the status of semantics. If semantics is an empirical discipline, one might expect that most changes are informed by empirical considerations. However, one may also note that the core notion of semantics, meaning, today is conceived of quite differently than in, say, the seventies. How can that be? How can that what semantics is about, be different now from what is was back then? Or is this perhaps an indication that semantics is not as empirical as it is often thought to be? Moreover, it seems that in some deep sense meaning as explicated in semantics and interpretation as studied in various philosophical approaches are strangely at odds. Meaning is what interpretation is concerned with: meaning is, at least so it seems, what in the process of interpretation language users try to recover (or analogously, what they try to convey in production). Yet, the way meaning is conceived of in semantics seems not to square all that neatly with how the process of interpretation is supposed to proceed. In particular it seems to lack some of the intrinsic features that various approaches to interpretation assume it to have. Given these discrepancies, one wonders how the two can be incorporated within a single theory. And that such a theory is desirable goes, it may be presumed, without saying These are the reasons that figure in this paper. At the background there are some others..

Links

PhilArchive

External links

  • This entry has no external links. Add one.
Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Formal Semantics: Origins, Issues, Early Impact.Barbara H. Partee - 2010 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 6 (1).
Holism: A Shopper's Guide.Jerry A. Fodor & Ernest Lepore - 1992 - Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell. Edited by Ernest LePore.
Meaning in motion.Martin Stokhof - 2000 - In von Heusinger & Urs Egli (eds.), Reference and Anaphoric Relations. Dordrecht: Kluwer. pp. 47-76.
Meaning and Interpretation.D. Prawitz (ed.) - 2002 - Konferenser.
Theory of meaning.Adrienne Lehrer - 1970 - Englewood Cliffs, N.J.,: Prentice-Hall. Edited by Keith Lehrer.
Meaning and interpretation: conference held in Stockholm, September 24-26, 1998.Dag Prawitz (ed.) - 2002 - [Stockholm]: Kungl. Vitterhets, historie och antikvitets akademien.
Meaning in Motion.Jeroen Groenendijk & Martin Stokhof - 2000 - In Klaus von Heusinger & Urs Egli (eds.), Reference and Anaphoric Relations. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 47--78.

Analytics

Added to PP
2010-12-22

Downloads
556 (#31,007)

6 months
39 (#93,882)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Martin Stokhof
University of Amsterdam

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Radical interpretation.Donald Davidson - 1973 - Dialectica 27 (1):314-328.
Radical Interpretation.Donald Davidson - 1973 - In John Heil (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: A Guide and Anthology. Oxford University Press.
Reasoning about information change.Jelle Gerbrandy & Willem Groeneveld - 1997 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 6 (2):147-169.

View all 6 references / Add more references