Action, knowledge and embodiment in Berkeley and Locke

Philosophical Explorations 21 (1):41-59 (2018)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Embodiment is a fact of human existence which philosophers should not ignore. They may differ to a great extent in what they have to say about our bodies, but they have to take into account that for each of us our body has a special status, it is not merely one amongst the physical objects, but a physical object to which we have a unique relation. While Descartes approached the issue of embodiment through consideration of sensation and imagination, it is more directly reached by consideration of action and agency: whenever we act upon the world, we act by moving our bodies. So if we can understand what an immaterialist such as Berkeley thinks about agency, we will have gone a fair way to understanding what he thinks about embodiment. §1 discusses a recent flurry of articles on the subject of Berkeley’s account of action. I choose to present Berkeley as a causal-volitional theorist not because I think it is the uniquely correct interpretation of the texts, but because I find it more philosophically interesting as a version of immaterialism. In particular, it raises the possibility of a substantive account of human embodiment which is completely unavailable to the occasionalist. §2 articulates an apparent philosophical problem for Berkeley qua causal-volitional theorist and show that Locke was aware of a related problem and had a solution of which Berkeley would have known. §3 distinguishes two interpretations of Berkeley’s famous denial of blind agency – as the assertion of a weak representational condition or a strong epistemic one – and provide evidence that there was a well-established debate about blind powers in the seventeenth century which took the metaphor of blindness as indicating an epistemic rather than merely representational failing. What remains to do in §4 is to consider whether Berkeley, with his own peculiar commitments, could in fact accept this account of agency.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,202

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Berkeley’s Lockean Religious Epistemology.Kenneth L. Pearce - 2014 - Journal of the History of Ideas 75 (3):417-438.
Berkeley's theory of abstract ideas.C. C. W. Taylor - 1978 - Philosophical Quarterly 28 (111):97-115.
Locke and Berkeley; a collection of critical essays.C. B. Martin - 1968 - Garden City, N.Y.,: Anchor Books. Edited by D. M. Armstrong.
Locke and Berkeley.C. B. Martin & David M. Armstrong (eds.) - 1968 - London,: University of Notre Dame Press.
Berkeley v. Locke on Primary Qualities.Barry Stroud - 1980 - Philosophy 55 (212):149-166.
Locke.E. J. Lowe - 1993 - New York: Routledge.

Analytics

Added to PP
2018-01-12

Downloads
85 (#191,493)

6 months
27 (#104,509)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Tom Stoneham
University of York

Citations of this work

Berkeley, God and the Succession of Ideas.Brad Thomson - 2021 - Dissertation, University of Ottawa

Add more citations

References found in this work

Actions.J. Hornsby - 1982 - Mind 91 (361):147-149.
Berkeley: An Interpretation.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1989 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
The Search after Truth.Nicholas Malebranche, Thomas M. Lennon & Paul J. Olscamp - 1982 - Philosophy of Science 49 (1):146-147.
Berkeley, human agency and divine concurrentism.Jeffrey K. McDonough - 2008 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 46 (4):pp. 567-590.

View all 24 references / Add more references