In Pedro Schmechtig & Martin Grajner (eds.), Epistemic Reasons, Norms, and Goals. De Gruyter. pp. 185-198 (2016)
Authors |
|
Abstract |
The notion of epistemic standards has gained prominence in the literature on the semantics of knowledge ascriptions. Defenders of Epistemic Contextualism claim that in certain scenarios the truth value of a knowledge-ascribing sentence of the form “S knows p (at t)”—where S is an epistemic subject and p is a proposition S is said to know at time t—can change even if S, p and t are assigned constant values. This sort of variability, contextualists claim, is due to the epistemic standards governing the context in which the knowledge ascription is uttered. While a specific knowledge ascription may be true when uttered in a context with “low” epistemic standards, it may be false when uttered in a context with “high” epistemic standards. The reason for this, as far as contextualists are concerned, is the context sensitivity of the verb “knows”. In standard semantics an expression is said to be context sensitive if and only if it expresses different contents (or intensions) relative to different contexts of utterance. Thus, as epistemic standards influence the content of “knows”, they play a crucial role in contextualist semantics. In this paper, I examine different conceptions of epistemic standards and argue that all but one lead to counterintuitive consequences. The conception which avoids these consequences, however, has the downside of seriously restricting the talk of “high” or “low” standards that is so frequent in discussions on the semantics of knowledge ascriptions.
|
Keywords | Epistemic Contextualism Epistemic Standards Knowledge |
Categories | (categorize this paper) |
Buy the book |
Find it on Amazon.com
|
DOI | 10.1515/9783110496765-010 |
Options |
![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() |
Download options
References found in this work BETA
No references found.
Citations of this work BETA
The epistemic significance of non-epistemic factors: an introduction.Andrea Robitzsch, Nikola Kompa & Igal Kvart - 2022 - Synthese 200 (3):1-11.
Similar books and articles
Think of the Children! Epistemic Justification and Cognitively Unsophisticated Subjects.Gregory Stoutenburg - 2017 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly.
Epistemic Invariantism and Contextualist Intuitions.Alexander Dinges - 2016 - Episteme 13 (2):219-232.
Epistemic Anxiety and Adaptive Invariantism.Jennifer Nagel - 2010 - Philosophical Perspectives 24 (1):407-435.
Managing Mental Standards with Corporate Citizenship Profiles.Laura Olkkonen & Vilma Luoma-aho - 2011 - Electronic Journal of Business Ethics and Organization Studies 16 (1):13-20.
A Review of “The Allure of Order: High Hopes, Dashed Expectations, and the Troubled Quest to Remake American Education ”. [REVIEW]Holly K. Brewster - 2014 - Educational Studies: A Jrnl of the American Educ. Studies Assoc 50 (5):525-529.
Trust, Authority and Epistemic Responsibility.Gloria Origgi - 2008 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 23 (1):35-44.
The Case Against Epistemic Relativism: Replies to Rosen and Neta.Paul A. Boghossian - 2007 - Episteme 4 (1):49-65.
Skepticism, Contextualism, and the Epistemic "Ordinary".Nancy Daukas - 2002 - Philosophical Forum 33 (1):63–79.
A Conceptual Analysis of Ethics Codes.Deni Elliott‐Boyle - 1985 - Journal of Mass Media Ethics 1 (1):22-26.
Analytics
Added to PP index
2016-10-29
Total views
40 ( #283,384 of 2,505,620 )
Recent downloads (6 months)
4 ( #169,997 of 2,505,620 )
2016-10-29
Total views
40 ( #283,384 of 2,505,620 )
Recent downloads (6 months)
4 ( #169,997 of 2,505,620 )
How can I increase my downloads?
Downloads