Philosophers should be interested in ‘common currency’ claims in the cognitive and behavioural sciences

South African Journal of Philosophy 33 (2):211-221 (2014)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

A recurring claim in a number of behavioural, cognitive and neuro-scientific literatures is that there is, or must be, a unidimensional ‘common currency’ in which the values of different available options are represented. There is striking variety in the quantities or properties that have been proposed as determinants of the ordering in motivational strength. Among those seriously suggested are pain and pleasure, biological fitness, reward and reinforcement, and utility among economists, who have regimented the notion of utility in a variety of ways, some of them incompatible. This topic deserves philosophical attention for at least the following reasons. Repeated invocation of the ‘common currency’ idiom isn’t merely terminological coincidence because most of the claims are competing explanations either of manifest pattern in choices, or of order in the processes producing choice. We can’t suppose that the different currency claims within each area are compatible, because there are significant obstacles to identifying pairs of members of either the ‘pattern’ or ‘process’ group. There are, finally, seriously opposed positions about the relationships between the pattern facts and the process facts. There are philosophical positions both favouring and opposing a common currency. But direct consideration of the abstract relationships between claims about common currencies across scientific settings, and the arguments for and against these claims, is relatively rare. There is, though, much of philosophical interest to be found here

Similar books and articles

Need there be a common currency for decision-making?David Spurrett - 2009 - South African Journal of Philosophy 28 (2):210-221.
Justifying group-specific common morality.Carson Strong - 2008 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 29 (1):1-15.
Innateness in cognitive science.Richard Samuels - 2004 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 8 (3):136-141.
Sociology and common sense.David Thomas - 1978 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 21 (1-4):1 – 32.
Introduction: Philosophy in and Philosophy of Cognitive Science.Andrew Brook - 2009 - Topics in Cognitive Science 1 (2):216-230.
Currency, Trade, and Commerce in Plato's Laws.Steven Skultety - 2006 - History of Political Thought 27 (2):189-205.
Metaphysical Arguments against Ordinary Objects.Amie L. Thomasson - 2006 - Philosophical Quarterly 56 (224):340 - 359.
The common premise for uncommon conclusions.C. A. J. Coady - 2013 - Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (5):284-288.

Analytics

Added to PP
2015-01-31

Downloads
559 (#30,870)

6 months
87 (#48,177)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

David Spurrett
University of KwaZulu-Natal

Citations of this work

Towards a Definition of Efforts.Olivier Massin - 2017 - Motivation Science 3 (3):230-259.
Does intragenomic conflict predict intrapersonal conflict?David Spurrett - 2016 - Biology and Philosophy 31 (3):313-333.
The Natural History of Desire.David Spurrett - 2015 - South African Journal of Philosophy 34 (3):304-313.

Add more citations

References found in this work

The Modularity of Mind.Robert Cummins & Jerry Fodor - 1983 - Philosophical Review 94 (1):101.
Consciousness Explained.Daniel C. Dennett - 1993 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (4):905-910.

View all 20 references / Add more references