The paradox of painful art

Journal of Aesthetic Education 41 (3):59-77 (2007)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Many of the most popular genres of narrative art are designed to elicit negative emotions: emotions that are experienced as painful or involving some degree of pain, which we generally avoid in our daily lives. Melodramas make us cry. Tragedies bring forth pity and fear. Conspiratorial thrillers arouse feelings of hopelessness and dread, and devotional religious art can make the believer weep in sorrow. Not only do audiences know what these artworks are supposed to do; they seek them out in pursuit of prima facie painful reactions.Traditionally, the question of why people seek out such experiences of painful art has been presented as the paradox of tragedy. Most solutions to the paradox of tragedy assume that the reason we seek out tragedies, horror films, melodramas, and the like is because they afford pleasureful experiences. From there, theorists attempt to account for the source of this pleasure, a pleasure assumed to be had from representations of events from which we do not derive pleasure in real life. I argue that this assumption is suspect: the motive for seeking out devotional religious art, melodrama, tragedy, and some horror is not clearly to find pleasure.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,386

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Art as Orientation.Norman Kreitman - 2011 - Metaphilosophy 42 (5):642-657.
The pleasures of documentary tragedy.Stacie Friend - 2007 - British Journal of Aesthetics 47 (2):184-198.
The feels good theory of pleasure.Aaron Smuts - 2011 - Philosophical Studies 155 (2):241-265.
Tragedy and Reparation.Elisa Galgut - 2009 - In Pedro Alexis Tabensky (ed.), The positive function of evil. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
Rubber Ring: Why do we listen to sad songs?Aaron Smuts - 2011 - In John Gibson & Noel Carroll (eds.), Narrative, Emotion, and Insight. Penn State UP. pp. 131.
Kames's Naturalist Aesthetics and the Case of Tragedy.Rachel Zuckert - 2009 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 7 (2):147-162.
The poetry and the pity: Hume's account of tragic pleasure.Elisa Galgut - 2001 - British Journal of Aesthetics 41 (4):411-424.
Art and negative affect.Aaron Smuts - 2009 - Philosophy Compass 4 (1):39-55.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
635 (#25,928)

6 months
57 (#74,349)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Aaron Smuts
Rhode Island College

Citations of this work

Imagination.Shen-yi Liao & Tamar Gendler - 2019 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Response-Dependence and Aesthetic Theory.Alex King - 2023 - In Chris Howard & R. A. Rowland (eds.), Fittingness. OUP. pp. 309-326.
Imagination.Tamar Szabó Gendler - 2012 - In Peter Adamson (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Let’s be Liberal: An Alternative to Aesthetic Hedonism.Antonia Peacocke - 2021 - British Journal of Aesthetics 61 (2):163-183.
Art and painful emotion.Matthew Strohl - 2018 - Philosophy Compass 14 (1):e12558.

View all 22 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

The Pleasures of Tragedy.Susan L. Feagin - 1983 - American Philosophical Quarterly 20 (1):95 - 104.
Enjoying Negative Emotions in Fictions.John Morreall - 1985 - Philosophy and Literature 9 (1):95-103.
Tragedy.Aaron Ridley - 2003 - In Jerrold Levinson (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics. Oxford University Press.
Nietzsche and the paradox of tragedy.Amy Price - 1998 - British Journal of Aesthetics 38 (4):384-393.
Aesthetic pleasure and pain.Marcia Muelder Eaton - 1973 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 31 (4):481-485.

Add more references