A Theory of Moods and Their Place in Our Science of Mind

Dissertation, The University of Wisconsin - Madison (2000)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

I present a computational theory of moods that identifies moods with biases in the operations of our cognitive functional architecture. Moods, I argue, are not representational states. They are biases in the operations of functional architecture-level processes such as memory and attention. Changes at the level of functional architecture have global effects on representation-level states and processes in ways that are independent of the semantic content of those states. My theory accounts for the intuition held by most philosophers that moods are 'objectless'. Moods are objectless because they are not intentional, representational states at all. It is also consistent with the empirical data on moods that demonstrate mood-related effects on processes such as memory, attention, problem-solving strategies and categorization. Moods have global effects on our mental lives in virtue of the fact that they are biases in the operations of those processes that shape and influence our thoughts, motivations and conscious experiences. ;I critically examine the traditional, philosophical 'cognitive theories' of affect and argue that this explanatory approach cannot yield a satisfactory account of moods. The failures of the cognitive approach suggest that moods are not representational states, but are processes that underlie and affect our representation level states and processes. Moods affect how we think, not what in particular we think about. This motivates my argument that moods are operations at the level of functional architecture. One of the implications of this view is that moods are cognitively impenetrable, according to Zenon Pylyshyn's criteria. ;I defend my theory of moods against alternative analyses, including Paul Griffiths' higher order functional state account, Robert Thayer's claim that moods are bodily states of arousal, and the view---held by psychologists such as William N. Morris and philosophers such as Michael Tye ---that moods are essentially feelings or sensory experiences. I argue that these analyses do not provide satisfactory accounts of mood. ;The computational analysis of mood I present in my dissertation offers a naturalistic, functional account of moods and places them within the context of other cognitive processes of interest to philosophers and cognitive scientists

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,386

External links

  • This entry has no external links. Add one.
Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Towards a computational theory of mood.Laura Sizer - 2000 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51 (4):743-770.
Affect without object: moods and objectless emotions.Carolyn Price - 2006 - European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 2 (1):49-68.
Folk, functional and neurochemical aspects of mood.Paul E. Griffiths - 1989 - Philosophical Psychology 2 (1):17-32.
The Self and Its Moods in Depression and Mania.Jennifer Radden - 2013 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 20 (7-8):7-8.
Intentionalism about Moods.Angela Mendelovici - 2013 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 2 (1):126-136.
How is a phenomenology of fundamental moods possible?Tanja Staehler - 2007 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 15 (3):415 – 433.
What feelings can't do.Laura Sizer - 2006 - Mind and Language 21 (1):108-135.
Basic moods.Craig DeLancey - 2006 - Philosophical Psychology 19 (4):527-538.
Toward a Phenomenology of Mood.Lauren Freeman - 2014 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 52 (4):445-476.

Analytics

Added to PP
2015-02-05

Downloads
2 (#1,787,337)

6 months
1 (#1,516,429)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Laura Sizer
Mount Holyoke College

Citations of this work

Good and Good For You: An Affect Theory of Happiness.Laura Sizer - 2010 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80 (1):133-163.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references