The use of cost-effectiveness by the National Institute for Health and Clinical Excellence (NICE): no(t yet an) exemplar of a deliberative process

Journal of Medical Ethics 34 (7):534-539 (2008)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Democratic societies find it difficult to reach consensus concerning principles for healthcare distribution in the face of resource constraints. At the same time the need for legitimacy of allocation decisions has been recognised. Against this background, the National Institute for Health and Clinical Excellence (NICE) aspires to meet the principles of procedural justice, specifically the conditions of accountability for reasonableness as espoused by Daniels and Sabin, that is, publicity, relevance, revisions and appeal, and enforcement. Although NICE has adopted a highly standardised approach and continuously publishes key documents on its website, its technology appraisal programme does not fulfil the publicity condition of accountability for reasonableness. Economic models are not made sufficiently transparent to enable public scrutiny, and decision criteria other than cost-effectiveness remain enigmatic. NICE’s reliance on cost-utility analysis and “plausible” cost-per-quality-adjusted life year (QALY) benchmarks further raises serious issues with regard to the relevance condition of accountability for reasonableness. This is illustrated by counterintuitive cost-per-QALY rankings that are difficult to justify using reflective equilibrium methods, and by the current debate surrounding expensive therapies for rare diseases (“orphan” treatments). In addition, an excessive focus on QALYs may stand in the way of exploiting the best available effectiveness evidence. The NICE mechanism for revision and appeals is also more restrictive than provided in accountability for reasonableness. As to the enforcement condition, no effective quality assurance processes are in place for technology assessments, and implementation of guidance remains imperfect. NICE, despite impressive efforts, appears to have a long way to go before meeting the conditions of accountability for reasonableness

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,219

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

A NICE fallacy.M. Quigley - 2007 - Journal of Medical Ethics 33 (8):465-466.
Impartiality and disability discrimination.Greg Bognar - 2011 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 21 (1):1-23.
An Integrated Approach to Resource Allocation.Louise M. Terry - 2004 - Health Care Analysis 12 (2):171-180.
Just Caring: Defining a Basic Benefit Package.L. M. Fleck - 2011 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 36 (6):589-611.
Who should manage care? The case for providers.John D. Stobo - 1997 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 7 (4):387-389.

Analytics

Added to PP
2010-09-13

Downloads
30 (#504,503)

6 months
4 (#698,851)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

References found in this work

Inequality Reexamined.Amartya Sen - 1927 - Oxford University Press UK.
Normative Ethics.Shelly Kagan - 1998 - Westview Press.
Normative Ethics.Shelly Kagan - 1998 - Mind 109 (434):373-377.
Justice, health, and healthcare.Norman Daniels - 2001 - American Journal of Bioethics 1 (2):2 – 16.

View all 11 references / Add more references