Reconsidering the common ratio effect: the roles of compound independence, reduction, and coalescing
Theory and Decision 77 (3):323-339 (2014)
Abstract
Common ratio effects should be ruled out if subjects’ preferences satisfy compound independence, reduction of compound lotteries, and coalescing. In other words, at least one of these axioms should be violated in order to generate a common ratio effect. Relying on a simple experiment, we investigate which failure of these axioms is concomitant with the empirical observation of common ratio effects. We observe that compound independence and reduction of compound lotteries hold, whereas coalescing is systematically violated. This result provides support for theories which explain the common ratio effect by violations of coalescing instead of violations of compound independence.Author's Profile
My notes
Similar books and articles
Common ratio using delay.Manel Baucells & Franz H. Heukamp - 2010 - Theory and Decision 68 (1-2):149-158.
Does learning diminish violations of independence, coalescing and monotonicity?Steven J. Humphrey - 2006 - Theory and Decision 61 (2):93-128.
Compound conditioning: Component strength in a compound CS as a function of test trial ratio.David C. Blouin & A. Grant Young - 1977 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 9 (4):291-293.
Measurement independence, parameter independence and non-locality.Iñaki San Pedro - 2014 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 4 (3):369-374.
Dewey, Hegel, and Causation.Jim Good & Jim Garrison - 2010 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 24 (2):101-120.
A computational model of ratio decidendi.L. Karl Branting - 1993 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 2 (1):1-31.
Revisiting Agency Theory: Evidence of Board Independence and Agency Cost from Bangladesh.Afzalur Rashid - 2015 - Journal of Business Ethics 130 (1):181-198.
When can statistical theories be causally closed?Balázs Gyenis & Miklós Rédei - 2002 - Foundations of Physics 34 (9):1285-1303.
Subjective brightness in relation to flash rate and the light-dark ratio.S. H. Bartley - 1938 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 23 (3):313.
The compound interest effect: Why cultural evolution is not niche construction.Eric Saidel - 2000 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23 (1):158-159.
In defence of metaphysical analyticity.Frank Hofmann & Joachim Horvath - 2008 - Ratio 21 (3):300-313.
Configural conditioning: Greater fear in rats to compound than component through overtraining of the compound.James H. Booth & L. J. Hammond - 1971 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 87 (2):255.
Analytics
Added to PP
2015-09-03
Downloads
34 (#345,863)
6 months
1 (#451,398)
2015-09-03
Downloads
34 (#345,863)
6 months
1 (#451,398)
Historical graph of downloads
Author's Profile
Citations of this work
Violations of coalescing in parametric utility measurement.Andreas Glöckner, Baiba Renerte & Ulrich Schmidt - 2020 - Theory and Decision 89 (4):471-501.
References found in this work
Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision Under Risk.D. Kahneman & A. Tversky - 1979 - Econometrica: Journal of the Econometric Society:263--291.
Microeconomic systems as experimental science.Vernon Smith - 1985 - American Economic Review 72 (5):923-955.
Utility theory: Axioms versus 'paradoxes'.Kenneth R. MacCrimmon & Stig Larsson - 1979 - In Maurice Allais & Ole Hagen (eds.), Expected Utility Hypotheses and the Allais Paradox. D. Reidel. pp. 333--409.
New paradoxes of risky decision making.Michael H. Birnbaum - 2008 - Psychological Review 115 (2):463-501.