Representation, Self-Representation, and the Passions in Descartes

Review of Metaphysics 48 (2):331 - 357 (1994)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

THAT DESCARTES WAS INTERESTED from the very start of his philosophic career in developing a method for problem-solving that could be applied generally to the solution of "unknowns" is well known. Also well known is the further development of the method by the introduction of the technique of hyperbolic doubt in his mature, metaphysical works, especially in the Meditations. Perhaps less widely appreciated is the important role that accounts of systems of signs played in the development of his early accounts of a method; it is crucial to the method that the elements of problems be identified and signified by simple and convenient signs that can then be arranged to display the relations among the known elements and the unknown solution. Commentators such as Michel Foucault have brought this interest in signification to our attention and shown the widespread importance of such projects in the seventeenth century. Few, however, have examined the relation between the early projects of signification and the later, metaphysical works. I suggest that one way to understand Descartes' metaphysical turn in his mature work is as an attempt to ground the accounts he has offered of signification in something further: representation, particularly mental representation. From the start, Descartes explains signification by reference to mental representation: a word, figure, or symbol signifies its objects by prompting the mind to think of those objects. Although Descartes offers detailed and comprehensive accounts in works such as the Rules for the Direction of the Mind of what constitutes effective and convenient systems of signification by way of the relations between signifying element, system, and the objects signified thereby, the mental operations that allow signification to operate, especially that of the "intuition of simple natures," is never fully explained. It remains to the mature phase of Descartes' career to crack open the basic operations of our thought by developing the full-fledged doctrine of ideas--a doctrine that makes explicit how an object is represented to a subject.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,386

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

The Epistemic Problem of Cartesian Passions.Ron Williston - 2003 - International Philosophical Quarterly 43 (3):309-332.
Never Let the Passions Be Your Guide: Descartes and the Role of the Passions.Shoshana Brassfield - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (3):459-477.
Mental representation: A functionalist view.Robert Van Gulick - 1982 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 63 (1):3-20.
Descartes' compositional theory of mental representation.David Landy - 2011 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 92 (2):214-231.
Representation of a representation: Reflections on las meninas.Rocco J. Gennaro - 2008 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 15 (9):47-50.
The Concept of Representation.Hanna Fenichel Pitkin (ed.) - 1967 - University of California Press.
Biosemantics.Ruth Garrett Millikan - 1989 - Journal of Philosophy 86 (July):281-97.

Analytics

Added to PP
2011-05-29

Downloads
32 (#488,786)

6 months
4 (#800,606)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Amy Schmitter
University of Alberta

Citations of this work

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references