Rational Self-Doubt and the Failure of Closure

Philosophical Studies 163 (2):428-452 (2013)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Closure for justification is the claim that thinkers are justified in believing the logical consequences of their justified beliefs, at least when those consequences are competently deduced. Many have found this principle to be very plausible. Even more attractive is the special case of Closure known as Single-Premise Closure. In this paper, I present a challenge to Single-Premise Closure. The challenge is based on the phenomenon of rational self-doubt – it can be rational to be less than fully confident in one's beliefs and patterns of reasoning. In rough outline, the argument is as follows: Consider a thinker who deduces a conclusion from a justified initial premise via an incredibly long sequence of small competent deductions. Surely, such a thinker should suspect that he has made a mistake somewhere. And surely, given this, he should not believe the conclusion of the deduction even though he has a justified belief in the initial premise.

Similar books and articles

Single premise deduction and risk.Maria Lasonen-Aarnio - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 141 (2):157 - 173.
Evidentialism and skeptical arguments.Dylan Dodd - 2012 - Synthese 189 (2):337-352.
When does epistemic closure fail?M. Yan - 2013 - Analysis 73 (2):260-264.
Interest-relative invariantism and knowledge from ignorance.Federico Luzzi - 2012 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 93 (1):31-42.
Knowledge and deductive closure.James L. White - 1991 - Synthese 86 (3):409 - 423.
Sensitivity, Safety, and Closure.Sven Bernecker - 2012 - Acta Analytica 27 (4):367-381.
Contextualism about justified belief.Ralph Wedgwood - 2008 - Philosophers' Imprint 8:1-20.
Closure Reconsidered.Yuval Avnur - 2012 - Philosophers' Imprint 12.
Epistemic Closure’s Clash with Technology in New Markets.Dennis R. Cooley - 2012 - Journal of Business Ethics 108 (2):181-199.
Counter-Closure.Federico Luzzi - 2010 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88 (4):673-683.
Ideal rationality and hand waving.Reed Richter - 1990 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 68 (2):147 – 156.
Two Notions of Epistemic Risk.Martin Smith - 2013 - Erkenntnis 78 (5):1069-1079.
Knowledge-Closure and Inferential Knowledge.Guido Melchior - 2010 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 10 (3):259-285.

Analytics

Added to PP
2010-10-23

Downloads
997 (#12,886)

6 months
156 (#18,500)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Joshua Schechter
Brown University

Citations of this work

Higher‐Order Evidence and the Limits of Defeat.Maria Lasonen-Aarnio - 2014 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88 (2):314-345.
Epistemic Modesty Defended.David Christensen - 2013 - In David Christensen & Jennifer Lackey (eds.), The Epistemology of Disagreement: New Essays. Oxford University Press. pp. 77.
Justified Inference.Ralph Wedgwood - 2012 - Synthese 189 (2):273-295.
Higher-Order Evidence.Daniel Whiting - 2021 - Analysis 80 (4):789-807.
Rational Reflection.David Christensen - 2010 - Philosophical Perspectives 24 (1):121-140.

View all 75 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Knowledge and its limits.Timothy Williamson - 2000 - New York: Oxford University Press.
Philosophical explanations.Robert Nozick - 1981 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Knowledge and lotteries.John Hawthorne - 2004 - New York: Oxford University Press.

View all 58 references / Add more references