"The whole is greater than the part." Mereology in Euclid's Elements

Logic and Logical Philosophy 25 (3):371-409 (2016)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The present article provides a mereological analysis of Euclid’s planar geometry as presented in the first two books of his Elements. As a standard of comparison, a brief survey of the basic concepts of planar geometry formulated in a set-theoretic framework is given in Section 2. Section 3.2, then, develops the theories of incidence and order using a blend of mereology and convex geometry. Section 3.3 explains Euclid’s “megethology”, i.e., his theory of magnitudes. In Euclid’s system of geometry, megethology takes over the role played by the theory of congruence in modern accounts of geometry. Mereology and megethology are connected by Euclid’s Axiom 5: “The whole is greater than the part.” Section 4 compares Euclid’s theory of polygonal area, based on his “Whole-Greater-Than-Part” principle, to the account provided by Hilbert in his Grundlagen der Geometrie. An hypothesis is set forth why modern treatments of geometry abandon Euclid’s Axiom 5. Finally, in Section 5, the adequacy of atomistic mereology as a framework for a formal reconstruction of Euclid’s system of geometry is discussed.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,386

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Port Royal: Filosofía de la Geometría.Jorge Alberto Molina - 2017 - Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 73 (3-4):1203-1238.
Thomas Reid’s geometry of visibles and the parallel postulate.Giovanni B. Grandi - 2005 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 36 (1):79-103.
Geometry and Spatial Intuition: A Genetic Approach.Rene Jagnow - 2003 - Dissertation, Mcgill University (Canada)
ARISTOTELIAN LOGIC AND EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRY.John Corcoran - 2014 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 20 (1):131-2.
John Dee on geometry: Texts, teaching and the Euclidean tradition.Stephen Johnston - 2012 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 43 (3):470-479.
The Euclidean Mousetrap.Jason M. Costanzo - 2008 - Idealistic Studies 38 (3):209-220.

Analytics

Added to PP
2018-02-06

Downloads
28 (#555,203)

6 months
9 (#290,637)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Klaus Robering
University of Southern Denmark

Citations of this work

Euclid’s Common Notions and the Theory of Equivalence.Vincenzo De Risi - 2020 - Foundations of Science 26 (2):301-324.
David Hilbert and the foundations of the theory of plane area.Eduardo N. Giovannini - 2021 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 75 (6):649-698.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Mathematics is megethology.David K. Lewis - 1993 - Philosophia Mathematica 1 (1):3-23.
Ontologies for Plane, Polygonal Mereotopology.Ian Pratt & Oliver Lemon - 1997 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38 (2):225-245.
The Aristotelian Continuum. A Formal Characterization.Peter Roeper - 2006 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 47 (2):211-232.

Add more references