Proportionality, Winner-Take-All, and Distributive Justice

Politics, Philosophy and Economics 8 (1):5-42 (2009)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

When faced with multiple claims to a particular good, what does distributive justice require? To answer this question, we need a substantive moral theory that will enable us assign relative moral weights to the parties' claims. But this is not all we need. Once we have assessed the moral weight of each party's claim, we still need to decide what method of distribution to employ, for there are two methods open to us. We could take the winner-take-all approach, and award the good to the party with the strongest claim. On the other hand, we could divide the good proportionally, according to the relative strength of each party's claim. Because the choice between these two methods of distribution can have a dramatic impact on the resulting pattern of distribution, the choice presents a question of justice. But this is a question of justice that is often overlooked. As a result, we currently employ the principle of proportionality far less often than justice actually requires. If we focus on the question of distributive method, however, we are not only better able to understand how certain reasons enter into our all-things-considered moral judgments, we are also able to explain some perplexing but common aspects of our moral beliefs: how rights can be said to have peremptory force, yet still be balanced against other important interests; how justice can sometimes require compromise, yet sometimes require victory; and how a moral theory can avoid being too demanding while still being demanding enough. Key Words: autonomy • equality • indivisibility • inviolability • weighted lotteries • rights.

Other Versions

No versions found

Similar books and articles

What Does Morality Require When We Disagree?Martin Marchman Andersen - 2019 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 16 (1):27-49.
Global Economy, Justice and Sustainability.Nigel Dower - 2004 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 7 (4):399-415.
Moral Demands and Ethical Theory: The Case of Consequentialism.Attila Tanyi - 2013 - In Barry Dainton & Howard Robinson, The Bloomsbury Companion to Analytic Philosophy. London: Bloomsbury Academic. pp. 500-527.
What we owe to distant others.Leif Wenar - 2003 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 2 (3):283-304.
Wittgensteinean Philosophy as Foundation of Moral Phenomenology.Dmitry Ivanov - 2008 - Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 10:199-205.
Egalitarianism, ideals, and cosmopolitan justice.Gillian Brock - 2005 - Philosophical Forum 36 (1):1–30.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
772 (#34,421)

6 months
160 (#28,776)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Mark R. Reiff
University of California, Davis

Citations of this work

Neutrality and Excellence.Mark R. Reiff - 2022 - In Mark McBride & Visa A. J. Kurki, Without Trimmings: The Legal, Moral, and Political Philosophy of Matthew Kramer. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. pp. 271-296.
Incommensurability and moral value.Mark R. Reiff - 2014 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 13 (3):237-268.
Fairness and Aggregation.A. C. Paseau & Ben Saunders - 2015 - Utilitas 27 (4):460-469.
Principles of stakes fairness in sport.Alexander Brown - 2015 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 14 (2):152-186.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Choices, Values, and Frames.Daniel Kahneman & Amos Tversky (eds.) - 2000 - Cambridge University Press.
War and massacre.Thomas Nagel - 1972 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 1 (2):123-144.
War and Massacre.Thomas Nagel - 1985 - In Lawrence A. Alexander, International Ethics: A Philosophy and Public Affairs Reader. Princeton University Press. pp. 53-75.
The consequentialist can recognise rights.Philip Pettit - 1988 - Philosophical Quarterly 38 (150):42-55.
Fairness.Bradford Hooker - 2005 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 8 (4):329-352.

Add more references