Aristotle’s second problem about a science of being qua being

Ancient Philosophy 37 (1):59-89 (2017)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

It is commonly assumed that Aristotle thinks that his claim that being exhibits a category-based pros hen structure, which he introduces to obviate the problem of categorial heterogeneity, is sufficient to defend the possibility of a science of being qua being. We, on the contrary, argue that Aristotle thinks that the pros hen structure is necessary only, but not sufficient, for this task. The central thesis of our paper is that Aristotle, in what follows 1003b19, raises a second problem for the possibility of the science of being qua being; and that he does not think that the resolution of the first, the category-based problem, is either necessary or sufficient for resolving this problem. This is the problem: how can a plurality of apparently primary kinds and their opposites (they include to hen, to on, to auto, to homoion, to heteron and to anhomoion) be the subject-matter of the science of being qua being? It has been argued that these kinds are per se attributes of ousia and that, therefore, this problem is not different from the first problem. This, we argue, is mistaken; for nowhere in Gamma 2 does Aristotle claim that unity is a per se attribute of ousia. Rather, he says that identity, similarity, etc. are per se attributes of being qua being and unity qua unity. Aristotle’s resolution of the second problem, we argue, is that most of these kinds are reducible to a single compound principle: being-and-unity. Being and unity, moreover, are themselves related to each other as primary ousia and consequent ousia; but, we argue, Aristotle leaves it open, in Gamma 2, which of the two is primary, and which is consequent ousia.

Links

PhilArchive

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Ancient Philosophical Poetics.Malcolm Heath - 2012 - Cambridge University Press.
Aristotle’s Topics. [REVIEW]Ian Bell - 2000 - Ancient Philosophy 20 (1):222-224.
Principles and Proofs. [REVIEW]William Wians - 1995 - Ancient Philosophy 15 (1):222-228.
Aristotle’s Advocacy of Non-Productive Action.Vasilis Politis - 1998 - Ancient Philosophy 18 (2):353-379.
Plato and Aristotle in Agreement? [REVIEW]Harold Tarrant - 2009 - Ancient Philosophy 29 (1):240-247.
Plato, Aristotle, and the purpose of politics.Kevin M. Cherry - 2012 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
Method and metaphysics: essays in ancient philosophy I.Jonathan Barnes - 2011 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by Maddalena Bonelli.

Analytics

Added to PP
2017-06-29

Downloads
711 (#21,857)

6 months
127 (#26,586)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author Profiles

Vasilis Politis
Trinity College, Dublin
Philipp Steinkrüger
Ruhr-Universität Bochum

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Aristotle: Metaphysics.Michael Loux - forthcoming - Ancient Philosophy.
Aristotle on Homonymy: Dialectic and Science.Julie K. Ward - 2007 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
Le problème de l'Être chez Aristote.[author unknown] - 1963 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 18 (1):77-77.
Aristotle's Metaphysics Books.C. C. W. Taylor & Christopher Kirwan - 1973 - Philosophical Quarterly 23 (91):162.

View all 15 references / Add more references