Hintikka’s Independence-Friendly Logic Meets Nelson’s Realizability

Studia Logica 106 (3):637-670 (2018)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Inspired by Hintikka’s ideas on constructivism, we are going to ‘effectivize’ the game-theoretic semantics for independence-friendly first-order logic, but in a somewhat different way than he did in the monograph ‘The Principles of Mathematics Revisited’. First we show that Nelson’s realizability interpretation—which extends the famous Kleene’s realizability interpretation by adding ‘strong negation’—restricted to the implication-free first-order formulas can be viewed as an effective version of GTS for FOL. Then we propose a realizability interpretation for IF-FOL, inspired by the so-called ‘trump semantics’ which was discovered by Hodges, and show that this trump realizability interpretation can be viewed as an effective version of GTS for IF-FOL. Finally we prove that the trump realizability interpretation for IF-FOL appropriately generalises Nelson’s restricted realizability interpretation for the implication-free first-order formulas.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,386

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Confined modified realizability.Gilda Ferreira & Paulo Oliva - 2010 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 56 (1):13-28.
Realizing Brouwer's sequences.Richard E. Vesley - 1996 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 81 (1-3):25-74.
Axiomatizing higher-order Kleene realizability.Jaap van Oosten - 1994 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 70 (1):87-111.
A general notion of realizability.Lars Birkedal - 2002 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (2):266-282.
Proof interpretations with truth.Jaime Gaspar & Paulo Oliva - 2010 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 56 (6):591-610.
Extensional realizability.Jaap van Oosten - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 84 (3):317-349.
A realizability interpretation for classical analysis.Henry Towsner - 2004 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 43 (7):891-900.
Is Hintikka's Logic First-Order?Matti Eklund & Daniel Kolak - 2002 - Synthese 131 (3):371-388.
Lifschitz' realizability.Jaap van Oosten - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (2):805-821.
Multiple realizability.Eric Funkhouser - 2007 - Philosophy Compass 2 (2):303–315.
A Realizability Interpretation for Classical Arithmetic.Jeremy Avigad - 2002 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (3):439-440.

Analytics

Added to PP
2017-10-14

Downloads
30 (#521,181)

6 months
9 (#295,075)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Stanislav Speranski
St. Petersburg State University

Citations of this work

HYPE: A System of Hyperintensional Logic.Hannes Leitgeb - 2019 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 48 (2):305-405.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Constructible falsity.David Nelson - 1949 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 14 (1):16-26.
Compositional semantics for a language of imperfect information.W. Hodges - 1997 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 5 (4):539-563.
Finite partially-ordered quantification.Wilbur John Walkoe Jr - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (4):535-555.
Finite Partially‐Ordered Quantifiers.Herbert B. Enderton - 1970 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 16 (8):393-397.
From if to bi.Samson Abramsky & Jouko Väänänen - 2009 - Synthese 167 (2):207 - 230.

View all 8 references / Add more references