Consent Under Pressure: The Puzzle of Third Party Coercion

Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17 (1):113-127 (2014)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Coercion by the recipient of consent renders that consent invalid. But what about when the coercive force comes from a third party, not from the person to whom consent would be proffered? In this paper I analyze how threats from a third party affect consent. I argue that, as with other cases of coercion, we should distinguish threats that render consent invalid from threats whose force is too weak to invalidate consent and threats that are legitimate. Illegitimate controlling third party threats render consent invalid just as they do in two party cases. However, knowing that the consent is invalid is not sufficient to tell the recipient of consent what she may or should do. I argue that when presented with a token of consent from someone whom she thinks is experiencing an illegitimate controlling threat, the recipient may act on that token if and only if doing so represents a reasonable joint decision for her and the victim of coercion. The appropriate action for someone faced with third party coercion therefore depends on the other options open to her and those open to the victim of coercion

Similar books and articles

Family coercion and valid consent.Stephen D. Mallary, Bernard Gert & Charles M. Culver - 1986 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 7 (2).
Consent and informational responsibility.Shaun D. Pattinson - 2009 - Journal of Medical Ethics 35 (3):176-179.
Informed consent: a primer for clinical practice.Deborah Bowman - 2012 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by John Spicer & Rehana Iqbal.
A defense of subsequent consent.Eric Chwang - 2009 - Journal of Social Philosophy 40 (1):117-131.
Rationally Justifying Political Coercion.Russell Hardin - 1990 - Journal of Philosophical Research 15:79-91.
Contracts.Brian Bix - 2010 - In Franklin G. Miller & Alan Wertheimer (eds.), The Ethics of Consent: Theory and Practice. Oxford University Press.
Autonomy, consent and the law.Sheila McLean - 2010 - New York, N.Y.: Routledge-Cavendish.
Is respect for autonomy defensible?James Wilson - 2007 - Journal of Medical Ethics 33 (6):353-356.

Analytics

Added to PP
2013-03-28

Downloads
578 (#29,631)

6 months
113 (#32,945)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Joseph Millum
University of St. Andrews

Citations of this work

Coercion.Scott Anderson - 2011 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
The Ethics of Allocating Uterine Transplants.Michelle J. Bayefsky & Benjamin E. Berkman - 2016 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 25 (3):350-365.

View all 13 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Famine, Affluence, and Morality.Peter Singer - 1972 - Oxford University Press USA.
Famine, affluence, and morality.Peter Singer - 1972 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 1 (3):229-243.
Coercion.Alan Wertheimer - 1990 - Princeton University Press.
Coercion.Robert Nozick - 1969 - In White Morgenbesser (ed.), Philosophy, Science, and Method: Essays in Honor of Ernest Nagel. St Martin's Press. pp. 440--72.
Harmless Wrongdoing.Joel Feinberg - 1990 - Oxford University Press.

View all 20 references / Add more references