On the State’s Exclusive Right to Punish

Law and Philosophy 41 (2):243-262 (2022)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In a characteristically iconoclastic essay, “Does the State Have a Monopoly to Punish Crime?”, Douglas Husak argues that the state’s moral right to punish crime is all but self-evident while its supposed monopoly on punishment is a fiction. Husak draws this bracing conclusion from a modest, quasi-Lockean premise – that persons and other entities have a right to impose stigmatizing deprivations on those who wrong them. This premise evokes John Locke’s far stronger claim that everyone enjoys a natural right to inflict potentially severe sanctions on any wrongdoer. The quasi-Lockean premise also evokes the familiar idea that all criminal wrongdoing is an attack on the broader community, and that law-breakers consequently owe a debt to society that they can repay through punishment. In this essay, I argue that the inferences Husak draws from the quasi-Lockean premise are unsound, but for reasons that reveal important lessons about the state’s right to punish crime and about the limits of what we can extract from the venerable idea that a central victim of criminal wrongdoing is the community as a whole. In Part II, I argue that the quasi-Lockean premise does not ground the state’s right to punish the kind of wrongs traditionally thought central to the criminal law, namely, wrongs perpetrated on individual human victims. In Part III, I answer Husak’s implicit challenge to describe a kind of stigmatizing deprivation – a kind of punishment – that the state alone has a right to inflict. I suggest that no entity but the state may inflict sanctions that constitute prima facie invasions of moral rights.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,386

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Review of Heidi Hurd, Moral Combat. [REVIEW]Thaddeus Metz - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (3):434-436.
Punishment and Justice.Jules Holroyd - 2010 - Social Theory and Practice 36 (1):78-111.
Authorization and the Right to Punish in Hobbes.Michael J. Green - 2015 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 97 (1):113-139.
Crime and Punishment.Lindsay Farmer - 2020 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 14 (2):289-298.
Judge and Punish: The Penal State on Trial.Geoffroy de Lagasnerie - 2018 - Stanford, California: Stanford University Press. Edited by Lara Vergnaud.
Rights within the social contract : Rousseau on punishment.Corey Brettschneider - 2011 - In Austin Sarat, Lawrence Douglas & Martha Merrill Umphrey (eds.), Law as Punishment/Law as Regulation. Stanford Law Books.
The Right to Punish in Thomas Hobbes’s Leviathan.Arthur Yates - 2014 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 52 (2):233-254.
Punishing the Oppressed and the Standing to Blame.Andy Engen - 2020 - Res Philosophica 97 (2):271-295.
The Crime of Self‐Solicitation.Benjamin Sachs - 2015 - Ratio Juris 28 (2):180-203.
Crime Victims and the Right to Punishment.David Alm - 2019 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 13 (1):63-81.
Forgiving and Forbearing Punishment.Patrick Lenta - 2020 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 34 (2):201-214.
Why punish the deserving?Douglas N. Husak - 1992 - Noûs 26 (4):447-464.

Analytics

Added to PP
2022-02-23

Downloads
42 (#370,011)

6 months
19 (#129,880)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Gabriel Mendlow
University of Michigan, Ann Arbor

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Rights.Leif Wenar - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Criminal attempt and the theory of the law of crimes.Lawrence C. Becker - 1974 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 3 (3):262-294.

Add more references