Intentions, reasons, and beliefs: Morals of the toxin puzzle

Philosophical Studies 68 (2):171 - 194 (1992)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In garden-variety instances of intentional action, according to a popular account, agents intend to perform actions of particular kinds, their intentions are based on reasons so to act, and the intentions issue in appropriate behaviour. On this account, the reasons that give rise to our intentions are reasons for action. Interesting questions for this view are raised by cases in which an agent seemingly has a reason to intend to do something while having no reason to do it. Can such reasons to intend issue in appropriate intentions? If so, can these intentions issue in corresponding intentional actions -- even though the agent has no reason to perform those actions? If these questions are properly given an affirmative answer, at least one popular thesis in the philosophy of action is false. One could not properly "define an intentional act as one which the agent does for a reason." A popular thesis about the explanation of intentional actions would be false as well -- namely, that explaining an intentional action (qua intentional) requires reference to reasons for action. My point of departure in this paper is a puzzle—Gregory Kavka's toxin puzzle(1983) -- in which agents seem to have an excellent reason to intend to A while having no reason at all to A. Generally, commentators on the puzzle have set their sights on questions about rational intentions. However, the puzzle raises difficult questions about intending itself and about the nature of intentional action. Showing that this is so is easy. Answering the question is more challenging.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,322

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Proximal intentions, intention-reports, and vetoing.Alfred Mele - 2008 - Philosophical Psychology 21 (1):1 – 14.
Friends, reasons and morals.David Gauthier - 2007 - In Bruno Verbeek (ed.), Reasons and Intentions. Ashgate.
How Action Governs Intention.Nishi Shah - 2008 - Philosophers' Imprint 8:1-19.
The Toxin Puzzle.Gregory S. Kavka - 1983 - Analysis 43 (1):33-36.
Reasons and Intentions.Bruno Verbeek (ed.) - 2007 - Ashgate.
Motivation-encompassing attitudes.Christopher G. Framarin - 2008 - Philosophical Explorations 11 (2):121 – 130.
Autonomous reasons for intending.Randolph Clarke - 2008 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86 (2):191 – 212.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
164 (#113,653)

6 months
11 (#226,803)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Alfred Mele
Florida State University

Citations of this work

Humean compatibilism.Helen Beebee & Alfred Mele - 2002 - Mind 111 (442):201-223.
Exercising Doxastic Freedom.Conor Mchugh - 2011 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88 (1):1-37.
Agents' abilities.Alfred R. Mele - 2003 - Noûs 37 (3):447–470.
Deciding to act.Alfred R. Mele - 2000 - Philosophical Studies 100 (1):81–108.

View all 19 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Intention.G. E. M. Anscombe - 1957 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Actions, Reasons, and Causes.Donald Davidson - 1963 - Journal of Philosophy 60 (23):685.
Change in View: Principles of Reasoning.Gilbert Harman - 1986 - Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press.

View all 19 references / Add more references