Venturing Beyond Analytic Philosophy's “Best” Arguments to the Implied Inadequacies of Its Metaphilosophical Intuitions

Southern Journal of Philosophy 51 (1):97-111 (2013)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Gary Gutting argues, in his recent book What Philosophers Know, that analytic philosophy provides a sizable collection of exemplary arguments that effectively yield a “disciplinary body of philosophical knowledge”—“metaphilosophy,” he names it—that is, specimens that define in a notably perspicuous way what we should understand as philosophical knowledge itself. He concedes weaknesses in the best-known specimens, and he admits that, generally, even the best specimens do not provide answers to the usual grand questions. I admire his treatment of the matter but argue that the metaphilosophical issues are, normally, of a much grander gauge than that of his sort of specimen; that they require a much more open, informal sort of inquiry and exchange than that of the distinctive rigor of the classic specimens themselves; that analytic philosophy, not uncharacteristically, tends to ignore the metaphilosophical issue or takes the validity of its method of argument for granted; and that the issue itself invites an appraisal of competing second-order conceptions of how philosophical argument proves fruitful. I proceed by way of the examination of cases drawn from Quine and Kripke

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,164

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

The Undefinability of Analytic Philosophy.Daniel Andler - 2000 - The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 6:267-285.
Metaphilosophy.Yuri Cath - 2011 - Oxford Bibliographies in Philosophy.
The Meanings of Life.David Schmidtz - 2002 - In Robert Nozick. Cambridge University Press.
Must we argue?Mark T. Nelson - 2004 - The Philosophers' Magazine 26 (26):41-42.
Philosophy, Logic, Science, History.Tim Crane - 2012 - Metaphilosophy 43 (1-2):20-37.
Pragmatistic influences in twentieth century finnish philosophy: From pre-analytic to post-analytic thought.Sami Pihlström - 2003 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 80 (1):511-535.
Intuitions and semantic theory.Henry Jackman - 2005 - Metaphilosophy 36 (3):363-380.
Forms of norms and validity.Vladimír Svoboda - 2003 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 80 (1):223-247.

Analytics

Added to PP
2013-03-01

Downloads
75 (#211,693)

6 months
3 (#857,336)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Joseph Margolis
Last affiliation: Temple University

Citations of this work

Replies to Margolis, Lycan, and Henderson.Gary Gutting - 2013 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 51 (1):133-140.
Précis of What Philosophers Know.Gary Gutting - 2013 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 51 (1):91-96.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Naming and Necessity: Lectures Given to the Princeton University Philosophy Colloquium.Saul A. Kripke - 1980 - Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Edited by Darragh Byrne & Max Kölbel.
Word and Object.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1960 - Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press.
Naming and Necessity.Saul Kripke - 1980 - Critica 17 (49):69-71.
Word and Object.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1960 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 17 (2):278-279.
Logic, semantics, metamathematics.Alfred Tarski - 1956 - Oxford,: Clarendon Press. Edited by John Corcoran & J. H. Woodger.

View all 14 references / Add more references