The significance of the theory analogy in the psychological study of concepts

Mind and Language 10 (1-2):45-71 (1995)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Many psychologists think that concepts should be understood on analogy with the terms of scientific theories, yet the significance of this claim has always been obscure. In this paper, I clarify the psychological content of the theory analogy, focusing on influential pieces by Susan Carey. Once plainly put, the analogy amounts to the view that a mental representation has its semantic properties by virtue of its role in a restricted knowledge structure. One of the commendable things about Carey's work is that, unlike many other psychologists who appeal to the theory analogy, she takes seriously the need to specify how these structures are constrained. At the same time, the constraints she offers are insufficient. Her account also faces challenges from work in the semantics of natural kind terms.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,139

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Number and natural language.Stephen Laurence & Eric Margolis - 2005 - In Peter Carruthers, Stephen Laurence & Stephen P. Stich (eds.), The Innate Mind: Structure and Contents. New York, US: Oxford University Press USA. pp. 1--216.
Acquiring a new concept is not explicable-by-content.Nicholas Shea - 2011 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (3):148 - 149.
Thought and syntax.William E. Seager - 1992 - Philosophy of Science Association 1992:481-491.
Structure-mapping: Directions from simulation to theory.Theodore Bach - 2011 - Philosophical Psychology 24 (1):23-51.
Representation, Meaning, and Thought.Grant Gillett - 1992 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
Category theory: The language of mathematics.Elaine Landry - 1999 - Philosophy of Science 66 (3):27.
Concepts.Eric Margolis & Stephen Laurence - 2011 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Concepts: Where Fodor went wrong.A. Levine & Mark H. Bickhard - 1999 - Philosophical Psychology 12 (1):5-23.
The twofold orientational structure of perception.John Dilworth - 2005 - Philosophical Psychology 18 (2):187-203.
The epistemological status of a naturalized epistemology.Ron Amundson - 1983 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 26 (3):333 – 344.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
96 (#171,674)

6 months
13 (#147,845)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Eric Margolis
University of British Columbia

Citations of this work

Concepts and Cognitive Science.Stephen Laurence & Eric Margolis - 1999 - In Eric Margolis & Stephen Laurence (eds.), Concepts: Core Readings. MIT Press. pp. 3-81.
How to acquire a concept.Eric Margolis - 1998 - Mind and Language 13 (3):347-369.
Précis of Doing without Concepts.Edouard Machery - 2010 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33 (2-3):195-206.
Précis of doing without concepts.Edouard Machery - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 149 (3):602-611.
Précis of Doing without Concepts.Edouard Machery - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 149 (3):401-410.

View all 11 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Naming and Necessity: Lectures Given to the Princeton University Philosophy Colloquium.Saul A. Kripke - 1980 - Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Edited by Darragh Byrne & Max Kölbel.
The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1962 - Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Edited by Ian Hacking.
The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Thomas Samuel Kuhn - 1962 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Edited by Otto Neurath.
Two Dogmas of Empiricism.W. Quine - 1951 - [Longmans, Green].

View all 50 references / Add more references