Epistemic restraint and the vice of curiosity

Philosophy 87 (2):239-259 (2012)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In recent years there has been wide-ranging discussion of epistemic virtues. Given the value and importance of acquiring knowledge this discussion has tended to focus upon those traits that are relevant to the acquisition of knowledge. This acquisitionist focus ignores or downplays the importance of epistemic restraint: refraining from seeking knowledge. In contrast, in many periods of history, curiosity was viewed as a vice. By drawing upon critiques of curiositas in Middle Platonism and Early Christian philosophy, we gain useful insights into the value and importance of epistemic restraint. The historical discussion paves the way for a clarification of epistemic restraint, one that distinguishes the morally relevant features of epistemic process, content, purpose, and context. Epistemic restraint is identified as an important virtue where our epistemic pursuits pose risks and burdens, where such pursuits have opportunity costs, where they are pursued for vicious purposes. But it is in the social realm where epistemic restraint has most purchase, epistemic restraint is important both because privacy is important and because being trusted are important. Finally, some suggestions are offered as to why epistemic restraint has not received the contemporary attention that it deserves

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,386

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Epistemic Badness.Anthony T. Flood - 2008 - Journal of Philosophical Research 33:253-262.
The Role of Non-Epistemic Values in Engineering Models.Sven Diekmann & Martin Peterson - 2013 - Science and Engineering Ethics 19 (1):207-218.
Epistemic responsibility.J. Angelo Corlett - 2008 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 16 (2):179 – 200.
Other–regarding epistemic virtues.Jason Kawall - 2002 - Ratio 15 (3):257–275.
Expressivism and Convention-Relativism about Epistemic Discourse.Allan Hazlett - forthcoming - In A. Fairweather & O. Flanagan (eds.), Naturalizing Epistemic Virtue. Cambridge University Press.
Epistemic normativity.Hilary Kornblith - 1993 - Synthese 94 (3):357 - 376.
On the Virtues and Plausibility of Feminist Epistemologies.Pieranna Garavaso & Nicla Vassallo - 2003 - Epistemologia, Rivista Italiana di Filosofia Della Scienza (1):99-131.

Analytics

Added to PP
2012-03-15

Downloads
125 (#141,919)

6 months
22 (#119,049)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Neil Manson
Lancaster University

Citations of this work

The virtue of curiosity.Lewis Ross - 2020 - Episteme 17 (1):105-120.
Deep Epistemic Vices.Ian James Kidd - 2018 - Journal of Philosophical Research 43:43-67..
The Curious Case of the Excellent Gossiper.Alkis Kotsonis - 2021 - Philosophia 50 (3):1207-1222.
Justified Evidence Resistance.Sven Bernecker - forthcoming - Acta Analytica:1-12.

View all 10 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Epistemic responsibility.Lorraine Code - 1987 - Hanover, N.H.: Published for Brown University Press by University Press of New England.
Why privacy is important.James Rachels - 1975 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 4 (4):323-333.

View all 14 references / Add more references