Science and Rationality for One and All

Ergo 1 (5):129-138 (2014)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

It seems obvious that a community of one thousand scientists working together to make discoveries and solve puzzles should arrange itself differently than would one thousand scientist-hermits working independently. Because of limited time, resources, and attention, an independent scientist can explore only some of the possible approaches to a problem. Working alone, each hermit would explore the most promising approaches. They would needlessly duplicate the work of others and would be unlikely to develop approaches which look unpromising but really have tremendous potential. Contrariwise, a large community can more rigorously explore the space of possible approaches. Most scientists should work on the most promising approaches, but a smaller number can be committed to approaches that initially look less promising. Exploratory work can reveal if one of those initially unpromising approaches has unrealized potential, and more scientists can adopt it once its potential becomes more apparent

Similar books and articles

Consensus and Evolution in Science.Gonzalo Munevar - 1986 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986:120 - 129.
Why science cannot be value-free.Agnieszka Lekka-Kowalik - 2010 - Science and Engineering Ethics 16 (1):33-41.
Siegel on the rationality of science.Brian S. Baigrie - 1988 - Philosophy of Science 55 (3):435-441.
Introduction: Aspects of Rationality.Alfred R. Mele & Piers Rawling - 2004 - In Alfred R. Mele & Piers Rawling (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Rationality. Oxford University Press.
Rationality and anemia (response to baigrie).Harvey Siegel - 1988 - Philosophy of Science 55 (3):442-447.
William Whewell: Problems of induction vs. problems of rationality.John Wettersten - 1994 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (2):716-742.
Could there be a science of rationality?Donald Davidson - 1995 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 3 (1):1-16.
Local and normative rationality of science: The 'content of discovery' rehabilitated. [REVIEW]Peter P. Kirschenmann - 1991 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 22 (1):61-72.

Analytics

Added to PP
2014-11-11

Downloads
273 (#71,061)

6 months
60 (#70,648)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

P. D. Magnus
State University of New York, Albany

Citations of this work

The scope of inductive risk.P. D. Magnus - 2022 - Metaphilosophy 53 (1):17-24.
Cautious realism and middle range ontology.P. D. Magnus - 2018 - Metascience 27 (3):365-370.
Scientific Rationality: Phlogiston as a Case Study.Jonathon Hricko - 2016 - In Timothy Joseph Lane & Tzu-Wei Hung (eds.), Rationality: Constraints and Contexts. London, U.K.: Elsevier Academic Press. pp. 37-59.

Add more citations