How Involved do You Want to be in a Non-symmetric Relationship?

Australasian Journal of Philosophy 92 (1):1-16 (2014)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

There are three different degrees to which we may allow a systematic theory of the world to embrace the idea of relatedness—supposing realism about non-symmetric relations as a background requirement. (First Degree) There are multiple ways in which a non-symmetric relation may apply to the things it relates—for the binary case, aRb ≠ bRa. (Second Degree) Every such relation has a distinct converse—for every R such that aRb there is another relation R* such that bR*a. (Third Degree) Each one of them applies in an order to the things it relates—with regard to the state that results from R's applying to a and b, either R applies to a first and b second, or it applies to b first and a second. Whereas the first degree is near-indubitable, embracing the second or third generates unwholesome consequences. The second degree embodies a commitment to the existence of a superfluity of distinct converses and states to which such relations give rise. The third degree embodies commitment to recherché facts of the matter about how the states that arise from the application of one non-symmetric relation compare to any other. It is argued that accounts that purport to offer an analysis of the first degree generate unwelcome second or third degree consequences. This speaks in favour of our adopting an account of the application of relations that's not an analysis at all, an account that takes the first degree as primitive.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,322

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

The Church-Rosser Property in Symmetric Combinatory Logic.Katalin Bimbó - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (2):536 - 556.
Semantics for dual and symmetric combinatory calculi.Katalin Bimbó - 2004 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 33 (2):125-153.
Determination of symmetric VL1 formulas: algorithm and program SYM4.Gerald M. Jenson - 1975 - Urbana: Dept. of Computer Science, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign.
Symmetric generalized galois logics.Katalin Bimbó & J. Michael Dunn - 2009 - Logica Universalis 3 (1):125-152.
Autonomy as rule by the self.Steven Weimer - 2014 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 92 (1):1-6.
Mental Files. [REVIEW]Laura Schroeter - 2013 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91 (4):829-830.

Analytics

Added to PP
2013-10-19

Downloads
208 (#92,856)

6 months
17 (#140,418)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Fraser MacBride
University of Manchester

Citations of this work

Properties.Francesco Orilia & Michele Paolini Paoletti - 2020 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Relations.Fraser MacBride - 2016 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Structures as Relations.Michele Paolini Paoletti - 2021 - Synthese 198 (Suppl 11):S2671-S2690.
Mereological Nominalism.Nikk Effingham - 2018 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 100 (1):160-185.

View all 19 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Knowledge and its limits.Timothy Williamson - 2000 - New York: Oxford University Press.
New work for a theory of universals.David K. Lewis - 1983 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61 (4):343-377.
Supervenience and mind: selected philosophical essays.Jaegwon Kim - 1993 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
The Principles of Mathematics.Bertrand Russell - 1903 - Cambridge, England: Allen & Unwin.
Knowledge and Its Limits.Timothy Williamson - 2000 - Philosophy 76 (297):460-464.

View all 42 references / Add more references