Logical Extensions of Aristotle’s Square

Logica Universalis 2 (1):167-187 (2008)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

.  We start from the geometrical-logical extension of Aristotle’s square in [6,15] and [14], and study them from both syntactic and semantic points of view. Recall that Aristotle’s square under its modal form has the following four vertices: A is □α, E is , I is and O is , where α is a logical formula and □ is a modality which can be defined axiomatically within a particular logic known as S5 (classical or intuitionistic, depending on whether is involutive or not) modal logic. [3] has proposed extensions which can be interpreted respectively within paraconsistent and paracomplete logical frameworks. [15] has shown that these extensions are subfigures of a tetraicosahedron whose vertices are actually obtained by closure of by the logical operations , under the assumption of classical S5 modal logic. We pursue these researches on the geometrical-logical extensions of Aristotle’s square: first we list all modal squares of opposition. We show that if the vertices of that geometrical figure are logical formulae and if the sub-alternation edges are interpreted as logical implication relations, then the underlying logic is none other than classical logic. Then we consider a higher-order extension introduced by [14], and we show that the same tetraicosahedron plays a key role when additional modal operators are introduced. Finally we discuss the relation between the logic underlying these extensions and the resulting geometrical-logical figures.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,202

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

The lattice of modal logics: An algebraic investigation.W. J. Blok - 1980 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 45 (2):221-236.
Visualizations of the square of opposition.Peter Bernhard - 2008 - Logica Universalis 2 (1):31-41.
On logics with coimplication.Frank Wolter - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 27 (4):353-387.
How to avoid deviance (in logic).Walter Sinnott-Armstrong & Amit Malhotra - 2002 - History and Philosophy of Logic 23 (3):215--36.
A Structuralist Account of Logic.Majda Trobok - 2008 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 8 (2):257-265.
The geometry of standard deontic logic.Alessio Moretti - 2009 - Logica Universalis 3 (1):19-57.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
50 (#304,573)

6 months
6 (#431,022)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Dominique Luzeaux
École Polytechnique

Citations of this work

The power of the hexagon.Jean-Yves Béziau - 2012 - Logica Universalis 6 (1-2):1-43.
Logical Geometries and Information in the Square of Oppositions.Hans5 Smessaert & Lorenz6 Demey - 2014 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 23 (4):527-565.
On the 3d visualisation of logical relations.Hans Smessaert - 2009 - Logica Universalis 3 (2):303-332.
Metalogical Decorations of Logical Diagrams.Lorenz Demey & Hans Smessaert - 2016 - Logica Universalis 10 (2-3):233-292.

View all 12 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

“Setting” n-Opposition.Régis Pellissier - 2008 - Logica Universalis 2 (2):235-263.
Modality and possibility in some intuitionistic modal logics.Josep M. Font - 1986 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 27 (4):533-546.
Introduction à la Logique Contemporaine.R. BLANCHE - 1957 - Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 16 (1):106-107.
Many-Valued Logic. [REVIEW]Elliott Mendelson - 1970 - Journal of Philosophy 67 (13):457-458.

Add more references