A Buddhist Take on Gilbert Ryle’s Theory of Mind

Asian Philosophy 24 (2):178-196 (2014)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Gilbert Ryle’s The Concept of Mind (1949/2002. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press) is generally considered a landmark in the quest to refute Cartesian dualism. The work contains many inspirational ideas and mainly posits behavioral disposition as the referent of mind in order to refute mind–body dualism. In this article, I show that the Buddhist theory of ‘non-self’ is also at odds with the belief that a substantial soul exists distinct from the physical body and further point out similarities between the Buddhist outlook and Ryle’s ideas in three parts. First, I illustrate that Ryle’s ‘category mistake’ has certain points in common with the Buddhist refutation of ‘self’. Within the Buddhist framework, referents such as ‘mind’ and ‘self’ are merely imputed terms. The presumed existence of an independent substance such as a ‘soul’, when considered in isolation from the expedient usage of the term ‘mind’, can therefore also be viewed as a ‘category mistake’. Second, attempting to solve the questions of ‘what mind is’ and ‘how mind operates’ are two entirely different approaches to the study of mind. I argue that it is necessary to focus on ‘knowing-how’ rather than ‘knowing-that’, if we are to gain a more comprehensive understanding of mind and avoid any kind of category mistake such as those that follow from isolating the physical properties of brain or drawing inferences from a mystical soul. Third, I aim to show why investigating mind from the perspective of ‘dispositions’ of behavior is a valid approach. The Buddhist concept of karma-vāsanā elucidates the habitual tendency to act or not act in various situations. Based on this theory, I argue that the workings of the human mind bears strong links to the formation of karma and as such have important axiological implications that cannot be ignored. I conclude by pointing out that Ryle’s insightful ideas could in certain ways be complemented by the Buddhist theory of mind. In my view, his philosophy is not only a mediator between Analytic Philosophy and Phenomenology, but could perhaps also be seen as a mediator between traditional Eastern systems of thought and contemporary philosophies of mind.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,349

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Ryle’s Dispositional Analysis of Mind and its Relevance.Desh Raj Sirswal - 2010 - Review Journal of Philosophy and Social Sciences (April, 2010):103-112.
GILBERRT RYLE ON DESCARTES' MYTH.Desh Raj Sirswal - 2007 - K.U. Research Journal of Arts and Humanities (Jan.-Dec.2007):81-86.
The Persistence of Category Mistakes in Psychology.Per Holth - 2001 - Behavior and Philosophy 29:203 - 219.
Ryle and Intentionality.Laird Addis - 2009 - Metaphysica 10 (1):49-63.
Philosophical Mind Studies.Desh Raj Sirswal - 2010 - Dissertation, Kurukshetra University, Kurukshetra
Professor Ryle on the concept of mind.Margaret Macdonald - 1951 - Philosophical Review 60 (January):80-90.
Aspects of Mind--Gilbert Ryle.Rene Meyer (ed.) - 1993 - Cambridge: Blackwell.
Gilbert Ryle: An Introduction To His Philosophy.William Lyons - 1980 - Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Sussex: Harvester Press.
The metaphysics of mind.Anthony Kenny - 1989 - New York: Oxford University Press.
GLOSSARY OF PHILOSOPHY OF MIND.Desh Raj Sirswal - 2009 - Philosophical Mind Studies.

Analytics

Added to PP
2014-05-29

Downloads
68 (#234,507)

6 months
17 (#142,297)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Kent Lin
Buddhist Tzu-Chi University

Citations of this work

Corrigendum.[author unknown] - 2014 - Asian Philosophy 24 (3):294-294.

Add more citations

References found in this work

The Concept of Mind.Gilbert Ryle - 1949 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 141:125-126.
The Concept of Mind.Gilbert Ryle - 1950 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 1 (4):328-332.

View all 30 references / Add more references