The phenomenological-existential comprehension of chronic pain: going beyond the standing healthcare models

Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine 9:2 (2014)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

A distinguishing characteristic of the biomedical model is its compartmentalized view of man. This way of seeing human beings has its origin in Greek thought; it was stated by Descartes and to this day it still considers humans as beings composed of distinct entities combined into a certain form. Because of this observation, one began to believe that the focus of a health treatment could be exclusively on the affected area of the body, without the need to pay attention to patient’s subjectivity. By seeing pain as a merely sensory response, this model was not capable of encompassing chronic pain, since the latter is a complex process that can occur independently of tissue damage. As of the second half of the twentieth century, when it became impossible to deny the relationship between psyche and soma, the current understanding of chronic pain emerges: that of chronic pain as an individual experience, the result of a sum of physical, psychological, and social factors that, for this reason, cannot be approached separately from the individual who expresses pain. This understanding has allowed a significant improvement in perspective, emphasizing the characteristic of pain as an individual experience. However, the understanding of chronic pain as a sum of factors corresponds to the current way of seeing the process of falling ill, for its conception holds a Cartesian duality and the positivist premise of a single reality. For phenomenology, on the other hand, the individual in his/her unity is more than a simple sum of parts. Phenomenology sees a human being as an intending entity, in which body, mind, and the world are intertwined and constitute each other mutually, thus establishing the human being’s integral functioning. Therefore, a real understanding of the chronic pain process would only be possible from a phenomenological point of view at the experience lived by the individual who expresses and communicates pain

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,322

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Chronic Pain - the Ethics of Care, Belief and Coping.Kate Jones - 2006 - Chisholm Health Ethics Bulletin 11 (4):6.
Chronic pain, compensation and clinical knowledge.George Mendelson - 1991 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 12 (3).
Pain, Chronic Pain, and Sickle Cell Chronic Pain.Ron Amundson - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (4):14 - 16.
Job and the Stigmatization of Chronic Pain.Daniel S. Goldberg - 2010 - Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 53 (3):425-438.
Pain and folk theory.C. R. Chapman, Y. Nakakura & C. N. Chapman - 2000 - Brain and Mind 1 (2):209-222.
No brain, no pain.Zsuzsanna Wiesenfeld-Hallin - 1997 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20 (3):486-487.

Analytics

Added to PP
2014-01-12

Downloads
53 (#293,652)

6 months
23 (#116,187)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Citations of this work

The social dimension of pain.Abraham Olivier - 2024 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 23 (2):375-408.
Transformation of the concept "subject" in the clinical discourse of philosophical anthropology.V. M. Skyrtach - 2018 - Антропологічні Виміри Філософських Досліджень 13.

Add more citations