Wolff, Baumgarten, and the Technical Idiom of Post-Leibnizian Philosophy of Mind

History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 21 (1):129-148 (2018)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Philosophers after Leibniz used a technical idiom to classify and explain the nature of mental content. Substantive philosophical claims were formulated in terms of this vocabulary, including claims about the nature of mental representations, concepts, unconscious mental content, and consciousness. Despite its importance, the origin and development of this vocabulary is insufficiently well understood. More specifically, interpreters have failed to recognize the existence of two distinct and influential versions of the post-Leibnizian idiom. These competing formulations used the same technical terms and taxonomic relations but assigned different connotations to those terms and employed different criteria for their application. This paper explains the two most influential versions of the post-Leibnizian idiom.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,202

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Between Wolffianism and Pietism: Baumgarten's Rational Psychology.Corey W. Dyck - 2018 - In Courtney D. Fugate & John Hymers (eds.), Baumgarten and Kant on Metaphysics. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. pp. 78-93.
Christian Wolff and Leibnizian Monads.Martin Schönfeld - 2002 - The Leibniz Review 12:131-135.
Christian Wolff and Leibnizian Monads.Martin Schönfeld - 2002 - The Leibniz Review 12:131-135.
Christian Wolff and Leibnizian Monads.Martin Schönfeld - 2002 - The Leibniz Review 12:131-135.
Kant and the Leibnizian Conception of Mind.Corey W. Dyck - 2006 - Dissertation, Boston College
Kant’s Lectures on Ethics and Baumgarten’s Moral Philosophy.Stefano Bacin - 2015 - In Lara Denis & Oliver Sensen (eds.), Kant's Lectures on Ethics: A Critical Guide. Cambridge University Press. pp. 15-33.
Forces and causes in Kant’s early pre-Critical writings.Eric Watkins - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (1):5-27.
Newton and Wolff: The Leibnizian reaction to the Principia, 1716-1763.Marius Stan - 2012 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 50 (3):459-481.
Du savoir, de la foi et de l'opinion de Wolff à Kant.Robert Theis - 2010 - Archives de Philosophie 73 (2):211-228.
Kant's critique of the Leibnizian philosophy : Contra the Leibnizians, but pro Leibniz.Anja Jauernig - 2008 - In Daniel Garber & Béatrice Longuenesse (eds.), Kant and the Early Moderns. Princeton University Press. pp. 41-63 (and 214-223 notes).

Analytics

Added to PP
2018-06-12

Downloads
19 (#750,145)

6 months
10 (#213,340)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Patrick R. Leland
University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign

Citations of this work

Kant and the determinacy of intuition.Jacob Browning - 2022 - European Journal of Philosophy 31 (1):65-79.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Kant and the Metaphysics of Causality.Eric Watkins - 2004 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
Inference and meaning.Wilfrid Sellars - 1953 - Mind 62 (247):313-338.
Kant and the Metaphysics of Causality.Eric Watkins - 2005 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 68 (3):624-626.
Wissenschaftslehre.Bernard Bolzano & Alois Höfler - 1837 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 22 (4):15-16.

View all 39 references / Add more references