Clive Bell’s "Metaphysical Hypothesis" and Everyday Aesthetics

Washington University Review of Philosophy 1:53-60 (2021)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Clive Bell’s Art, published in 1913, is widely seen as a founding document in contemporary aesthetics. Yet his formalism and his attendant definition of art as “significant form” is widely rejected in contemporary art discourse and in the philosophy of art. In this paper I argue for a reconsideration of his thought in connection with current discussions of “the aesthetics of everyday life.” Although some, notably Allen Carlson, have argued against application of Bell’s formalism to the aesthetics of everyday life, I claim that this is based on an interpretation of the concept that is overly narrow. First, Li Zehou offers an interpretation of “significant form” that allows in sedimented social meaning. Second, Bell himself offers a more complex theory of significant form by way of his “metaphysical hypothesis,” one that stresses perception of significant form outside the realm of art. Bell’s idea that the artist can perceive significant form in nature allows for significant form to not just be the surface-level formal properties of things. It stresses depth, although a different kind than the cognitive scientific depth Carlson wants. This is a depth that is consistent with the anti-dualism of Spinoza, Marx and Dewey. Reinterpreting Bell in this direction, we can say we are moved by certain relations of lines and colors because they direct our minds to the hidden aspect of things, the spiritual side of the material world referred to by Spinoza and developed by Dewey in his concept of experience. Bell hardly “reduces the everyday to a shadow of itself,” as Carlson puts it, since the everyday, as experienced by the artist or the aesthetically astute observer, has, or potentially has, deep meaning. If we reject Bell’s dualism and his downgrading of sensuous experience, we can rework his idea of pure form to refer to an aspect of things detached, yes, from practical use, but not from particularity or sedimented meaning, not purified of all associations.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,202

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Clive Bell.Lawrence Harvey - 2009 - The Philosophers' Magazine 44:94-96.
Clive Bell.Lawrence Harvey - 2009 - The Philosophers' Magazine 44:94-96.
Clive Bell's Eye.Rosalind Ekman - 1976 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 34 (3):344-345.
Everyday Aesthetics and Photography.Thomas Leddy - 2014 - Aisthesis: Pratiche, Linguaggi E Saperi Dell’Estetico 7 (1):45-62.
Clive Bell.From Clive Bell - 1999 - In Nigel Warburton (ed.), Philosophy: The Basic Readings. Routledge.
Clive Bell's Eye.William G. Bywater - 1975 - Wayne State University Press.
Cracking the Division Bell.Michael C. LaBossiere - 1996 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 10 (2):25-33.
Shadow of Spirit.Clive Marsh - 1993 - Philosophy Now 8:43-44.
Clive bell's aesthetic: Tradition and significant form.Thomas M. Mclaughlin - 1977 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 35 (4):433-443.
Clive bell.Herbert Read - 1965 - British Journal of Aesthetics 5 (2):107-110.
Clive bell and aesthetic emotion.R. Meager - 1965 - British Journal of Aesthetics 5 (2):123-131.

Analytics

Added to PP
2021-09-16

Downloads
18 (#781,713)

6 months
3 (#880,460)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Thomas W. Leddy
San Jose State University

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references