Obligation as Optimal Goal Satisfaction

Journal of Philosophical Logic 47 (4):579-609 (2018)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Formalising deontic concepts, such as obligation, prohibition and permission, is normally carried out in a modal logic with a possible world semantics, in which some worlds are better than others. The main focus in these logics is on inferring logical consequences, for example inferring that the obligation O q is a logical consequence of the obligations O p and O. In this paper we propose a non-modal approach in which obligations are preferred ways of satisfying goals expressed in first-order logic. To say that p is obligatory, but may be violated, resulting in a less than ideal situation s, means that the task is to satisfy the goal p ∨ s, and that models in which p is true are preferred to models in which s is true. Whereas, in modal logic, the preference relation between possible worlds is part of the semantics of the logic, in this non-modal approach, the preference relation between first-order models is external to the logic. Although our main focus is on satisfying goals, we also formulate a notion of logical consequence, which is comparable to the notion of logical consequence in modal deontic logic. In this formalisation, an obligation O p is a logical consequence of goals G, when p is true in all best models of G. We show how this non-modal approach to the treatment of deontic concepts deals with problems of contrary-to-duty obligations and normative conflicts, and argue that the approach is useful for many other applications, including abductive explanations, defeasible reasoning, combinatorial optimisation, and reactive systems of the production system variety.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,423

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

A logical analysis of the relationship between commitment and obligation.Churn-Jung Liau - 2001 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 10 (2):237-261.
Reasoning About Permitted Announcements.P. Balbiani & P. Seban - 2011 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 40 (4):445-472.
Contrary-to-duty obligations.Henry Prakken & Marek Sergot - 1996 - Studia Logica 57 (1):91 - 115.
Obligations and prohibitions in Talmudic deontic logic.M. Abraham, D. M. Gabbay & U. Schild - 2011 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 19 (2-3):117-148.
A logic of comparative obligation.Mark A. Brown - 1996 - Studia Logica 57 (1):117 - 137.
Models as Universes.Brice Halimi - 2017 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 58 (1):47-78.
Adaptive Logic as a Modal Logic.Patrick Allo - 2013 - Studia Logica 101 (5):933-958.
Logical Consequence in Modal Logic.John Corcoran & George Weaver - 1969 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 10 (4):370-384.
Modal Logics and Philosophy.Rod Girle - 2000 - [Durham]: Mcgill-Queen's University Press.
Is modal logic logic?Gilbert Harman - 1972 - Philosophia 2 (1-2):75-84.

Analytics

Added to PP
2017-07-05

Downloads
34 (#459,882)

6 months
4 (#800,606)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

Hyperintensionality and Normativity.Federico L. G. Faroldi - 2019 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer Verlag.
A bimodal simulation of defeasibility in the normative domain.Tomer Libal, Matteo Pascucci, Leendert van der Torre & Dov Gabbay - 2020 - In Proceedings of FCR-2020. CEUR Workshop Proceedings. pp. 41-54.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Collected papers.Charles S. Peirce - 1931 - Cambridge,: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
A logic for default reasoning.Ray Reiter - 1980 - Artificial Intelligence 13 (1-2):81-137.
Reasons as Defaults.John F. Horty - 2012 - Oxford, England: Oup Usa.
Agency and deontic logic.John Horty - 2001 - New York: Oxford University Press.
Reasons as Defaults.John Horty - 2007 - Philosophers' Imprint 7:1-28.

View all 49 references / Add more references