Consequentialism, Moral Responsibility, and the Intention/ Foresight Distinction

Utilitas 6 (2):201 (1994)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In many recent discussions of the morality of actions where both good and bad consequences foreseeably ensue, the moral significance of the distinction between intended and foreseen consequences is rejected. This distinction is thought to bear on the moral status of actions by those who support the Doctrine of Double Effect. According to this doctrine, roughly speaking, to perform an action intending to bring about a particular bad effect as a means to some commensurate good end is impermissible, while performing an action where one intends only this good end and merely foresees the bad as an unintended sideeffect may be permissible. Consequentialists argue that this is a distinction which makes no moral difference to the evaluation of the initial act in the two cases, given that the overall consequences are the same in each case. In this paper we aim to show that a standard consequentialist line of argument against the moral relevance of the intention/foresight distinction fails. Consequentialists commonly reject the moral relevance of this distinction on the grounds that there is no asymmetry in moral responsibility between intending and foreseeing evil. We argue that even if this claim about moral responsibility is correct, it does not entail, as many Consequentialists believe, that there is no moral asymmetry between acts of intended and foreseen evil. We go on to argue that those consequentialists who do concede the moral relevance of the intention/foresight distinction at the level of agent evaluations cannot consistently make such a concession, and that such a position is in any case untenable, because it entails a complete severance of important conceptual connections between act and agent evaluations

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,386

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Intention, foresight, and mutilation: A response to Giebel.Christopher Kaczor - 2007 - International Philosophical Quarterly 47 (4):477-482.
Foresight, intention and responsibility.Arthur R. Miller - 1989 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 27 (1):71-85.
In Defense of the Intention/Foresight Distinction.Mark P. Aulisio - 1995 - American Philosophical Quarterly 32 (4):341 - 354.
On the Importance of the Intention/Foresight Distinction.Mark P. Aulisio - 1996 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 70 (2):189-205.
The Origin of Foresight.Martin Amsteus - 2012 - World Futures 68 (6):390 - 405.
Legal and moral responsibility.Antony Duff - 2009 - Philosophy Compass 4 (6):978-986.
Intention and responsibility in double effect cases.David K. Chan - 2000 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 3 (4):405-434.
Consequentialize This.Campbell Brown - 2011 - Ethics 121 (4):749-771.

Analytics

Added to PP
2010-08-30

Downloads
118 (#148,663)

6 months
9 (#295,075)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Justin Oakley
Monash University

Citations of this work

No Plaything: Ethical Issues Concerning Child-pornography.Peter J. King - 2008 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 11 (3):327-345.
Intention and responsibility in double effect cases.David K. Chan - 2000 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 3 (4):405-434.

View all 6 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Anarchy, State, and Utopia.Robert Nozick - 1974 - Philosophy 52 (199):102-105.
Modern Moral Philosophy.G. E. M. Anscombe - 1958 - Philosophy 33 (124):1 - 19.
The Methods of Ethics.Henry Sidgwick - 1907 - Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 30 (4):401-401.
Punishment and Responsibility.H. L. A. Hart - 1968 - Philosophy 45 (172):162-162.

View all 32 references / Add more references