Psychosis and Intelligibility

Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 28 (3):233-249 (2021)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

When interacting with other people, we assume that they have their reasons for what they do and believe, and experience recognizable feelings and emotions. When people act from weakness of will or are otherwise irrational, what they do can still be comprehensible to us, since we know what it is like to fall for temptation and act against one’s better judgment. Still, when someone’s experiences, feelings and way of thinking is vastly different from our own, understanding them becomes increasingly difficult. Delusions and psychosis are often seen as marking the end of intelligibility. In this paper, I argue first for the importance of seeing other people as intelligible as long as this is at all possible. Second, I argue, based on both previous literature and my own lived experience, that more psychotic phenomena than previously thought can be rendered at least somewhat intelligible. Besides bizarre experiences like illusions, hallucinations and intense feelings of significance, I also explain what it is like to lose one’s bedrock, and how this loss impacts which beliefs one has reason to reject. Finally, I give an inside account of some disturbances of reason, and show that there are important similarities between certain psychotic reasoning problems and common non-pathological phenomena.

Similar books and articles

Universal Gravitation and the (Un)Intelligibility of Natural Philosophy.Matias Slavov - 2019 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 101 (1):129-157.
Heidegger, Dreyfus, and the Intelligibility of Practical Comportment.Leslie A. MacAvoy - 2019 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 50 (1):68-86.
On the grammar of "psychosis".Markus L. A. Heinimaa - 2000 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 3 (1):39-46.
Schmitz, Jordan, and Wallace on Intelligibility.Nicholas Lobkowicz - 1984 - Review of Metaphysics 38 (1):57 - 68.
Temporality in Psychosis: Loss of Lived Time in an Alien World.Marina Marren - 2015 - The Humanistic Psychologist 43 (2):148-159.
Psychotic consciousness.Peter Chadwick - 2001 - International Journal of Social Psychiatry 47 (1):52-62.
Response to Hubert Dreyfus and Nancy Sherman.Jonathan Lear - 2009 - Philosophical Studies 144 (1):81 - 93.
Positive Functions of Psychosis.Willem H. J. Martens - 2010 - Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 41 (2):216-233.

Analytics

Added to PP
2021-06-10

Downloads
515 (#34,529)

6 months
188 (#14,182)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Sofia Jeppsson
Umeå University

Citations of this work

Overcoming Hermeneutical Injustice in Mental Health: A Role for Critical Phenomenology.Rosa Ritunnano - 2022 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 53 (3):243-260.
Radical psychotic doubt and epistemology.Sofia Jeppsson - forthcoming - Philosophical Psychology 36 (8):1482-1506.
A Wide-Enough Range of ‘Test Environments’ for Psychiatric Disabilities.Sofia Jeppsson - 2023 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 94:39-53.
Rationalism.Jakob Ohlhorst - forthcoming - In Ema Sullivan Bissett (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Delusion. Routledge.

View all 10 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

What we owe to each other.Thomas Scanlon - 1998 - Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
What is it like to be a bat?Thomas Nagel - 1974 - Philosophical Review 83 (October):435-50.
Freedom and Resentment.Peter Strawson - 1962 - Proceedings of the British Academy 48:187-211.
Creating the Kingdom of Ends.Christine M. Korsgaard - 1996 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.

View all 27 references / Add more references