John Rawls and Liberal Neutrality

Interpretation 27 (2):105-128 (2000)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

This dissertation addresses liberal neutrality, particularly in the work of John Rawls. ;Because "neutrality" is a protean term, I first clarify a number of its senses. The heart of the dissertation, however, is the treatment of Rawls' neutralism as it develops from A Theory of Justice through Political Liberalism. Goodness as rationality, Rawls' account of the good in Theory, is a modified version of the idea that the good is the desired. Goodness as rationality supports the account of primary goods, which operate in the original position. I show that without that support from goodness as rationality, the primary goods are not necessarily good. So Theory needs goodness as rationality, but Rawls' failure to argue for it leaves his view incomplete. And because Rawls' argument for his principles of justice assumes this essentially utilitarian account of the good, the neutrality of Theory is as limited as that of utilitarianism. ;The central argument of Political Liberalism is that disagreements between comprehensive doctrines normally are reasonable; coercion should not be practiced, where fundamental matters are at stake, on those who reasonably reject the justification for that coercion; and therefore positions on fundamentals should receive justifications neutral between comprehensive doctrines. This argument implicitly supports the neutrality between ends exhibited by goodness as rationality, and so if successful would fill a hole in Rawls' view. But the argument is inadequate. It assumes for itself a special status, that no reasonable person can reject it. But reasonable persons can reject both premises of the argument. Thus Rawls' later view cannot achieve the privileged moral and epistemological status it needs in order to be satisfactory on its own terms. ;I also address Rawls' account of public reason. I argue that public reason inevitably will be affected by comprehensive doctrines in ways that should trouble Rawls, and that his account requires people to assert for political purposes what they in fact reasonably reject. Finally, Rawls' Constitutional theory attempts an unsuccessful synthesis of opposing traditions of Constitutional interpretation.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,122

External links

  • This entry has no external links. Add one.
Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Why Liberal Neutralists Should Accept Educational Neutrality.Matt Sensat Waldren - 2013 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 16 (1):71-83.
Justice, Liberalism, and Responsibility.Steven Paul Scalet - 1999 - Dissertation, The University of Arizona
A third principle of justice.Burleight T. Wilkins - 1997 - The Journal of Ethics 1 (4):355-374.
Four Versions of Liberalism.Beth Ann Rosenschein - 1988 - Dissertation, Stanford University
Towards a Reclamation of Substantive Liberalism.John Patrick Rudisill - 2001 - Dissertation, The University of Iowa
On John Rawls and Public Reason.Jonah David Murdock - 1998 - Dissertation, Northwestern University

Analytics

Added to PP
2015-02-02

Downloads
1 (#1,841,214)

6 months
1 (#1,346,405)

Historical graph of downloads

Sorry, there are not enough data points to plot this chart.
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

Public Reason and Abortion: Was Rawls Right After All?Robbie Arrell - 2019 - The Journal of Ethics 23 (1):37-53.
Realizing 'Political' Neutrality.Robert Westmoreland - 2011 - Law and Philosophy 30 (5):541-573.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references