Massively representational minds are not always driven by goals, conscious or otherwise

Behavioral and Brain Sciences 37 (2):145-146 (2014)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

This article has no associated abstract. (fix it)

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,386

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Leaping to conclusions: Connectionism, consciousness, and the computational mind.Dan Lloyd - 1991 - In Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson (eds.), Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 444--459.
Can a machine be conscious? How?Stevan Harnad - 2003 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 10 (4-5):67-75.
Brains are not conscious.John L. Tienson - 1987 - Philosophical Papers 16 (November):187-93.
Perception and other minds.Fred I. Dretske - 1973 - Noûs 7 (1):34-44.
The Mind in Nature.C. B. Martin - 2007 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
Consciousness, agents and the knowledge game.Luciano Floridi - 2005 - Minds and Machines 15 (3):415-444.
Computationalism and the problem of other minds.Stuart S. Glennan - 1995 - Philosophical Psychology 8 (4):375-88.

Analytics

Added to PP
2014-09-23

Downloads
56 (#279,626)

6 months
8 (#342,364)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author Profiles

Bryce Huebner
Georgetown University
Robert D. Rupert
University of Colorado, Boulder

References found in this work

Alief and Belief.Tamar Szabó Gendler - 2008 - Journal of Philosophy 105 (10):634-663.
Alief in Action (and Reaction).Tamar Szabó Gendler - 2008 - Mind and Language 23 (5):552--585.
Pushmi-pullyu representations.Ruth Garrett Millikan - 1995 - Philosophical Perspectives 9:185-200.

View all 9 references / Add more references