Untying a Knot From the Inside Out: Reflections on the “Paradox” of Supererogation

Social Philosophy and Policy 27 (2):29-63 (2010)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In his 1958 seminal paper “Saints and Heroes”, J. O. Urmson argued that the then dominant tripartite deontic scheme of classifying actions as being exclusively either obligatory, or optional in the sense of being morally indifferent, or wrong, ought to be expanded to include the category of the supererogatory. Colloquially, this category includes actions that are “beyond the call of duty” (beyond what is obligatory) and hence actions that one has no duty or obligation to perform. But it is a controversial category. Some have argued that the concept of supererogation is paradoxical because on one hand, supererogatory actions are (by definition) supposed to be morally good, indeed morally best, actions. But then if they are morally best, why aren't they morally required, contrary to the assumption that they are morally optional? In short: how can an action that is morally best to perform fail to be what one is morally required to do? The source of this alleged paradox has been dubbed the ‘good-ought tie-up’. In our article, we address this alleged paradox by first making a phenomenological case for the reality of instances of genuine supererogatory actions, and then, by reflecting on the relevant phenomenology, explaining why there is no genuine paradox. Our explanation appeals to the idea that moral reasons can play what we call amerit conferring role. The basic idea is that moral reasons that favor supererogatory actions function to confer merit on the actions they favor—they play a merit conferring role—and can do without also requiring the actions in question. Hence, supererogatory actions can be both good and morally meritorious to perform yet still be morally optional. Recognition of a merit conferring role unties the good-ought tie up, and (as we further argue) there are good reasons, independent of helping to resolve the alleged paradox, for recognizing this sort of role that moral reasons may play.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,423

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Self-regarding supererogatory actions.Jason Kawall - 2003 - Journal of Social Philosophy 34 (3):487–498.
Supererogation, Imperfect Duty and the Structure of Moral Action.Jon J. Scott - 1995 - Dissertation, University of Ottawa (Canada)
Amorality.Dale Dorsey - 2016 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 19 (2):329-342.
Duties Beyond The Call Of Duty.Heidi Hurd - 1998 - Jahrbuch für Recht Und Ethik 6.
Promising and supererogation.Jason Kawall - 2005 - Philosophia 32 (1-4):389-398.
Acting for the right reasons.Julia Markovits - 2010 - Philosophical Review 119 (2):201-242.
Moral Talking and Moral Living.Jonathan Harrison - 1963 - Philosophy 38 (146):315-328.

Analytics

Added to PP
2010-06-17

Downloads
272 (#71,843)

6 months
44 (#88,857)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author Profiles

Mark Timmons
University of Arizona
Terry Horgan
University of Arizona

Citations of this work

Supererogation and Conditional Obligation.Daniel Muñoz & Theron Pummer - 2022 - Philosophical Studies 179 (5):1429–1443.
There Are No Purely Aesthetic Obligations.John Dyck - 2021 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 102 (4):592-612.
Willpower Satisficing.Richard Yetter Chappell - 2019 - Noûs 53 (2):251-265.
Supererogation, Sacrifice, and the Limits of Duty.Alfred Archer - 2016 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 54 (3):333-354.

View all 35 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Ethical Intuitionism.Michael Huemer - 2005 - New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Moral reasons.Jonathan Dancy - 1993 - Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell.
Saints and heroes.J. O. Urmson - 1958 - In Abraham Irving Melden (ed.), Essays in moral philosophy. Seattle: University of Washington Press.
Moral Reasons.Jonathan Dancy - 1993 - Philosophy 69 (267):114-116.

View all 36 references / Add more references