On the nature of the lexicon: the status of rich lexical meanings

Journal of Linguistics (forthcoming)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The main goal of this paper is to show that there are many phenomena that pertain to the construction of truth-conditional compounds that follow characteristic patterns, and whose explanation requires appealing to knowledge structures organized in specific ways. We review a number of phenomena, ranging from non-homogenous modification and privative modification to polysemy and co-predication that indicate that knowledge structures do play a role in obtaining truth-conditions. After that, we show that several extant accounts that invoke rich lexical meanings to explain such phenomena face problems related to inflexibility and lack of predictive power. We review different ways in which one might react to such problems as regards lexical meanings: go richer, go moderately richer, go thinner, and go moderately thinner. On the face of it, it looks like moderate positions are unstable, given the apparent lack of a clear cutoff point between the semantic and the conceptual, but also that a very thin view and a very rich view may turn out to be indistinguishable in the long run. As far as we can see, the most pressing open questions concern this last issue: can there be a principled semantic/world knowledge distinction? Where could it be drawn: at some upper level (e.g. enriched qualia structures) or at some basic level (e.g. constraints)? How do parsimony considerations affect these two different approaches? A thin meanings approach postulates intermediate representations whose role is not clear in the interpretive process, while a rich meanings approach to lexical meaning seems to duplicate representations: the same representations that are stored in the lexicon would form part of conceptual representations. Both types of parsimony problems would be solved by assuming a direct relation between word forms and (parts of) conceptual or world knowledge, leading to a view that has been attributed to Chomsky (e.g. by Katz 1980) in which there is just syntax and encyclopedic knowledge.

Links

PhilArchive

External links

  • This entry has no external links. Add one.
Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

On Travis cases.Agustin Vicente - 2012 - Linguistics and Philosophy 35 (1):3-19.
A Look at Meaning Eliminativism.Luca Gasparri - 2013 - Philosophy Study 3 (11).
Verdi is the puccini of music.John Woods & Brent Hudak - 1992 - Synthese 92 (2):189 - 220.
Grammar, Ontology, and the Unity of Meaning.Ulrich Reichard - 2013 - Dissertation, University of Durham
Lexical meaning.M. Lynne Murphy - 2010 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
Some reflections on the lexical meaning.Alina-Mihaela Bursuc - 2012 - Human and Social Studies 1 (1):95-106.
The dynamic lexicon in a truth-conditional framework; or how to have Your cake and eat it.John Collins - 2019 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 62 (3):326-343.

Analytics

Added to PP
2020-04-11

Downloads
396 (#48,333)

6 months
86 (#48,933)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Agustin Vicente
University of the Basque Country

Citations of this work

Proprietary linguistic meaning.Tim Pritchard - 2022 - Synthese 200 (5):1-20.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Literal Meaning.François Récanati - 2002 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
New horizons in the study of language and mind.Noam Chomsky - 2000 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
Lexical meaning in context: a web of words.Nicholas Asher - 2011 - New York: Cambridge University Press.

View all 23 references / Add more references