Formal Notes on the Substitutional Analysis of Logical Consequence

Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 61 (2):317-339 (2020)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Logical consequence in first-order predicate logic is defined substitutionally in set theory augmented with a primitive satisfaction predicate: an argument is defined to be logically valid if and only if there is no substitution instance with true premises and a false conclusion. Substitution instances are permitted to contain parameters. Variants of this definition of logical consequence are given: logical validity can be defined with or without identity as a logical constant, and quantifiers can be relativized in substitution instances or not. It is shown that the resulting notions of logical consequence are extensionally equivalent to versions of first-order provability and model-theoretic consequence. Every model-theoretic interpretation has a substitutional counterpart, but not vice versa. In particular, in contrast to the model-theoretic account, there is a trivial intended interpretation on the substitutional account, namely, the homophonic interpretation that does not substitute anything. Applications to free logic, and theories and languages other than set theory are sketched.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,349

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

The Formal-Structural View of Logical Consequence.Gila Sher - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (2):241-261.
Logical Consequence and Natural Language.Michael Glanzberg - 2015 - In Colin R. Caret & Ole T. Hjortland (eds.), Foundations of Logical Consequence. Oxford University Press. pp. 71-120.
Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence.Jared Bates - 1999 - Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1):47-54.
Logical Truth and Consequence.Christopher Noel Foster - 1999 - Dissertation, University of Kansas
The formal-structural view of logical consequence.Gila Sher - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (2):241-261.
Logical Consequence: Its nature, structure, and application.Colin R. Caret & Ole T. Hjortland - 2015 - In Colin R. Caret & Ole T. Hjortland (eds.), Foundations of Logical Consequence. Oxford University Press.
Concepts of Logical Consequence.Darcy Allen Cutler - 1997 - Dissertation, The University of Western Ontario (Canada)
The Medieval Theory of Consequence.Stephen Read - 2012 - Synthese 187 (3):899-912.
Models and Logical Consequence.Gil Sagi - 2014 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 43 (5):943-964.

Analytics

Added to PP
2020-04-09

Downloads
64 (#247,260)

6 months
11 (#226,803)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Volker Halbach
Oxford University

Citations of this work

Naïve Truth and the Evidential Conditional.Iacona Andrea & Lorenzo Rossi - 2024 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 1:1-26.
Substitutional Validity for Modal Logic.Marco Grossi - 2023 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 64 (3):291-316.
Classical Determinate Truth I.Kentaro Fujimoto & Volker Halbach - 2024 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 89 (1):218-261.
Naïve Truth and the Evidential Conditional.Andrea Iacona & Lorenzo Rossi - 2024 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 53 (2):559-584.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Logical Pluralism.J. C. Beall & Greg Restall - 2005 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press. Edited by Greg Restall.
Axiomatizing Kripke’s Theory of Truth.Volker Halbach & Leon Horsten - 2006 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (2):677 - 712.
Existence and contingency.Timothy Williamson - 2000 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100 (1):117–139.
Über den Begriff der Logischen Folgerung.Alfred Tarski - 1937 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 2 (2):83-84.
Maximal consistent sets of instances of Tarski’s schema.Vann McGee - 1992 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 21 (3):235 - 241.

View all 11 references / Add more references