Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves

Abstract

In my paper, I argue that Kant identifies a good will with an end in itself. I provide textual support for this interpretation from several of Kant’s works. I also reconstruct two arguments from the Groundwork to support this interpretation. First, because a good will is a negative end, i.e. one that limits the kind of subjective ends that can be adopted, it is the right logical type of end to be identified with an end in itself. Second, Kant claims both that a good will is the only thing that has absolute worth and that an end in itself has absolute worth. The focus of my paper is to defend this interpretation from the objection that it has morally repugnant consequences. Commentators including Henry Allison argue that if Kant identifies a good will with an end in itself then only rational beings that possess a good will must be treated as ends in themselves and never as mere means. I agree with Allison that Kant could not have intended to exclude the many rational beings lacking a good will from the fullest sort of moral consideration. I disagree with Allison that the good will interpretation has this consequence. I argue that Allison’s objection can be met by attending to a distinction Kant makes between two kinds of ends in themselves. I claim that Kant identifies a good will with an actual end in itself. This kind of end has absolute worth and the status of an end in itself. I claim that Kant identifies all rational beings as practical ends in themselves. This kind of end does not have absolute worth or the status of an end in itself but must be treated as if it did. I draw a detailed analogy between Kant’s argument for the formula of humanity as an end in itself and his argument that rational beings are practically free to demonstrate that Kant makes this distinction. I claim that just as rational beings are practically rather than actually free in virtue of necessarily representing themselves as free, they are practically rather than actually ends in themselves in virtue of necessarily representing themselves as ends in themselves. Furthermore, just as rational beings are bound by the laws of freedom whether they are actually or practically free, they are bound by moral laws whether they are actually or practically ends in themselves. It follows that the moral law to treat others always as an end and never as mere means applies to all rational beings in virtue of necessarily representing themselves as ends in themselves, whether or not they have a good will and are actually ends in themselves. Thus, recognizing the distinction between two kinds of ends in themselves renders the good will interpretation of Kant compatible with the claim that all rational beings must be treated always as an end and never as mere means. KEYWORDS: Kant's practical ethics, good will, end in itself, freedom, humanity.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,139

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

  • Only published works are available at libraries.

Similar books and articles

Animals in the Kingdom of Ends.Heather M. Kendrick - 2010 - Between the Species 13 (10):2.
Kantian-Consequentialism.Darrell L. Johnson - 1992 - Dissertation, Southern Illinois University at Carbondale
Autonomy and the highest good.Lara Denis - 2005 - Kantian Review 10:33-59.
Setting ends for oneself through reason.Andrews Reath - 2009 - In Simon Robertson (ed.), Spheres of Reason. Oxford University Press.
The Value of Humanity.L. Nandi Theunissen - 2020 - Oxford University Press.
An Examination of Kant's Duties of Right and Their Moral Basis.Joyce Lazier Baldwin - 2004 - Dissertation, The University of Nebraska - Lincoln
What We Should Treat as an End in Itself.Richard Curtis Dean - 1999 - Dissertation, The University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill
The Kingdom of Ends.Susan Robbins - 1993 - Dissertation, Temple University
Two conceptions of the highest good in Kant.Andrews Reath - 1988 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 26 (4):593-619.
Stoic autonomy.John M. Cooper - 2003 - Social Philosophy and Policy 20 (2):1-29.
Can Kant have an account of moral education?Kate A. Moran - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 43 (4):471-484.

Analytics

Added to PP
2015-04-02

Downloads
28 (#524,295)

6 months
1 (#1,346,405)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references