Interest, Nature, and Art

Review of Metaphysics 31 (4):580-603 (1978)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In this paper, however, I will argue that Kant’s restriction of interest to natural rather than artistic beauty should not be taken as a basic aspect of his aesthetic theory, and thus need not affect our assessment of that theory’s more basic claims. First, I will suggest that Kant’s theory of intellectual interest is not really necessary to explain what we ordinarily mean by an interest in beautiful objects—a desire to preserve them for repeated experience, a motivation for our efforts to see them and our willingness to pay for them, and the like—and that the exclusion of art from a special moral interest thus does not leave our general interest in its objects unexplained. But, I will also argue, Kant’s own theory of art and our response to it actually allows beauties of art to have just as much claim to this intellectual interest as do objects of natural beauty. Kant’s differentiation of natural and artistic beauty with regard to moral interest turns on an ambiguity in the concept of nature itself, as well as on Kant’s assumptions that art, unlike nature, is a product of an intention to produce pleasure through determinately conceived objects, and that our response to art, again unlike that to nature, must be connected to a recognition of its intentionality. But Kant’s own theory of artistic creation—his theory of genius—undermines the force of the first of these assumptions, for it teaches us that art, while indeed the product of intentional activity, also calls upon the use of a natural talent that deserves our admiration as much as any other gift of nature. In other words, Kant’s own view of the complexity of artistic intentions forbids the simple differentiation of art and nature that he employs in §42, and while Kant’s theory of aesthetic response does not clearly preclude the view that our response to art must take into account the intentions with which art is produced, it also hardly entails this view. This may have been obscured from Kant by the indeterminacy of his own key concept of the freedom of the imagination, but, I will suggest, this freedom might actually have to be extended to the case of art if it is to work even in Kant’s paradigmatic case of natural beauty. Thus, on Kant’s own account the beauties of nature and of art are far more intimately connected, both in their own ontological status and in our response to them, than his theory of intellectual interest concedes.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,386

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Kant and the Aesthetics of Nature.Alexander Rueger - 2007 - British Journal of Aesthetics 47 (2):138-155.
Essays in Kant's Aesthetics.Ted Cohen & Paul Guyer - 1983 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 41 (3):337-340.
Kant and the Claims of Taste.Paul Guyer - 1979 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
A Kantian Critique Of Positive Aesthetics Of Nature.Jonathan Parker - 2010 - American Society for Aesthetics Graduate E-Journal 2 (2):1-7.
A new look at Kant's view of aesthetic testimony.Keren Gorodeisky - 2010 - British Journal of Aesthetics 50 (1):53-70.
Musik und Zeit bei Kant.Susanne Herrmann-Sinai - 2009 - Kant Studien 100 (4):427-453.
The aesthetic appreciation of nature.Malcolm Budd - 1996 - British Journal of Aesthetics 36 (3):207-222.
Values of Beauty: Historical Essays in Aesthetics.Paul Guyer - 2005 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
On Kant's Theory of Aesthetics (in Czechoslovakian).Vlastimil Zatka - 1993 - Estetika: The European Journal of Aesthetics 30 (3):48-59.

Analytics

Added to PP
2011-05-29

Downloads
51 (#306,042)

6 months
5 (#638,139)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Paul Guyer
Brown University

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references